Werner Ulrich's Home Page:  Ulrich's Bimonthly

Formerly "Picture of the Month"

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

July-August 2016
Operations Research and Critical Systems Thinking
An Integrated Perspective, Part 1: O.R. as Applied Systems Thinking

   Ulrich's Bimonthly (formerly Picture of the Month)

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

Abstract: What does good practice of applied science and expertise mean, and what can critical systems thinking (CST) do for it? Taking the example of operations research (O.R.), also called "operational research" (OR) in the United Kingdom, this two-part essay proposes new answers to both questions. It reaches out to the wider community of applied researchers in general and O.R. professionals in particular, and explains from their perspective what CST is all about and why it matters for good practice. Part 1 first reviews the idea and history of systems thinking in O.R., as a basis for properly situating CST within O.R. It then offers a comparative, non-partisan account of the two strands of CST, critical systems heuristics (CSH) and total systems intervention (TSI), and identifies their combined potential in an ability to enhance the contextual sophistication of O.R. The prevalent but inaccurate notion of the history of O.R. as a linear evolution from "hard" to "soft" and "critical" systems thinking is replaced by an integrated perspective of O.R. as applied systems thinking.

Keywords: operations research (O.R.); operational research (OR); history of O.R.; philosophy of O.R.; practice of O.R.; professional practice; professional education; professionalism; expertise; applied research; applied science; applied systems thinking; science education; critical systems thinking; critical pragmatism; critical systems heuristics (CSH); problem structuring; research education; research practice, competence in practice; practical reason; practical reasoning; practical rationality; reflective practice.

Suggested citation: Ulrich, W. (2012). Operations research and critical systems thinking: an integrated perspective. Part 1: O.R. as applied systems thinking. Journal of the Operational Research Society 63(9), pp. 1228-1247. Post-publication version in Ulrich's Bimonthly, July-August 2016.
[HTML] http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_july2016.html
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_july2016.pdf

Note concerning references: For readers who would like to cite the original version, the following text includes hints at the corresponding original pagination as follows: [/ pp.]. For example, [/1229] means that p. 1229 begins here. The same pagination marks will be found in the PDF file (see the "PDF file" link in the upper right-hand column). Please note that the present HTML version has been edited a bit beyond the PDF version, which was previously prepared for the author's Academia.edu site in August, 2015, and in the interest of consistent citations is made available here in that earlier form.

 

Previous |

 Next

For a hyperlinked overview of all issues of "Ulrich's Bimonthly" and the previous "Picture of the Month" series, see the site map

PDF file

Note: With this and the subsequent Bimonthly I continue the undertaking, initiated with the November-December 2015 issue, of offering pre- or post-publication versions of previously published papers that thus far are available in PDF format only or are not available in open-access mode at all. The topic takes up the theme of the last two Bimonthlies, of critically pragmatic practice in the field of operations research, with a particular focus on the role of critical systems thinking.

 

Introduction

Operations research (O.R.) is a remarkably multifaceted and successful profession. Operations researchers work for and with a great variety of clients. They are asked to intervene in a great variety of problem situations often characterized by high degrees of complexity and diversity. They bring to these situations strong analytical and consultancy skills. And finally, they rely on a sophisticated tool basket of quantitative and qualitative methods and have a solid educational and professional background. Although O.R. practitioners share many of these skills with other professionals engaged in industrial, commercial, and governmental problem solving and planning – among them public policy analysts, management consultants, evaluation researchers, information systems designers, crisis managers, and trustees – they have available some very specialized competencies in quantitative modeling and numerate analysis. These other professions also have their particular skills. What in the end distinguishes a profession is whether beyond specialized skills, practitioners also have a good portion of those more generalist skills on which depends the competent application of specialized skills in the first place, generalist skills such as situating problems properly in their contexts, understanding the needs of the parties involved, facilitating mutual understanding and conflict resolution, and so on. Good O.R. practice thus depends on a wealth of skills and services that its practitioners offer and which together make up O.R.'s remarkable profile of competencies.

Rich practice, impoverished accounts Against this rich profile of competencies that matter, the accounts one finds of O.R. practice in the literature often look impoverished. O.R. texts and journals often convey the impression that O.R. is a rather narrow discipline of quantitative modeling and numerate analysis, in which the many other skills that matter for successful problem solving and professional intervention hardly seem to play any role. The systems literature makes a partial exception in that it discusses the value of one particular generalist skill, systems thinking and its quest for a whole-systems perspective, for a proper understanding and handling of problem situations. But at the same time, systems-theoretical accounts of O.R. often draw on the same impoverished picture (not to say, caricature) of O.R. to argue their own case. Within the systems literature, the game repeats itself in that each school of systems thinking tends to give an overly narrow picture of the others, as if the reality of problem situations could ever be captured through a merely quantitative perspective (a caricature of [/1229] "hard" systems thinking) or a merely subjectivist perspective (a caricature of "soft" systems thinking), or even through a merely emancipatory perspective (a caricature of "critical" systems thinking). Furthermore, as if to make things worse, "classical" O.R. (a caricature of what O.R. was from the very beginning) is aligned with "hard" systems thinking as if the very real successes of O.R. could be explained in this way (a caricature of the nature of professional practice, applied science, and applied systems thinking). Based on such caricatures of O.R. as applied "hard" systems thinking, one can then apparently introduce soft and critical systems thinking as alternative paradigms that will save O.R. theory and practice from their unenlightened state and make them evolve away from hard towards soft and critical systems thinking.

Rethinking the relation of O.R. and systems thinking   This is not how the present essay understands progress in O.R. and systems practice. It takes as its starting point the simple idea that professional practice is what professionals do in practice rather than what some theorists say it is. If this is so, one must doubt whether the rich universe of professional practice exercised in the names of operations research and applied systems thinking can be adequately captured and explained in terms of either hard or soft or critical systems thinking or any other particular theoretical paradigm. It would seem that the relationship of O.R. and systems thinking needs to be understood differently.

The position this paper takes is that both O.R. theory and O.R. practice have from the outset relied on an understanding of professional intervention, and of the role of systems thinking in it, that was considerably more sophisticated than the now prevalent caricatures of "classical" O.R. and its supposed evolution from "hard" to "soft" and "critical" systems thinking. It is advisable, then, to ground an adequate understanding of the ties between O.R. and CST in these three partial efforts:

  1. a review of the original connection of O.R. and systems thinking with regard to their shared notion of competent practice;
  2. a systematic and non-partisan examination of the methodological potential of critical systems thinking as it can be found in its two main contemporary strands, critical systems heuristics (CSH) and total systems intervention (TSI) or creative holism (CH); and
  3. a clarification of the concept of good O.R. practice with a view to the challenges professionals face in practice.

Only on this triple basis can we hope to understand the relation between O.R. and CST in a way that is theoretically adequate and conducive to good practice. This, then, is what the present two-part essay proposes to do. It should be clear though that in pursuing this effort, the aim is not to assess or criticize what O.R. professionals do in practice and how well they do it. No claim is involved to do justice to the multifaceted efforts of those many skilled professionals who do their best in everyday practice to bring the skills and tools of O.R. to bear on the problems of the people and organizations they serve. Nor does the paper claim to give a history of O.R. that would come in any way close to doing justice to the field's rich history of ideas. The paper's only aim is to examine in a somewhat balanced and systematic manner what CST might contribute to O.R.'s future profile.

O.R. and systems thinking in retrospect

Since the very beginning of operations research in efforts to improve military operations such as radar-supported aircraft interception shortly before and during World War II, one of the main ideas – apart from working in interdisciplinary teams – was to study operations "as a whole," that is, to improve their overall system performance rather than to maximize the performance of each and every component activity. Expanding the approach to non-military applications in industrial production, business administration, and civil government, the first internationally recognized textbook defined O.R. as "the application of scientific methods, techniques, and tools to problems involving the operations of a system so as to provide those in control of the system with optimum solutions to the problem" (Churchman et al, 1957; pp. 8f and 18; similar formulations were used by some other early and often-cited accounts of O.R., e.g., by Beer, 1959, and Ackoff and Sasieni, 1968).

Two concepts of "optimum solution"  It is to the credit of the wide-spread use and success of quantitative O.R. techniques that the notion of an "optimum solution" today makes us think of mathematical optimization in the first place; but this is not how these pioneers understood the concept. Their notion of optimality was a systems-theoretical rather than a technical or mathematical notion. We might need to translate it today as the search for an overall balance between multiple, changing, conflicting, partly incommensurable and partly immeasurable or intangible objectives, as distinguished from a notion of optimality that aims at maximizing or minimizing the quantitative value of an objective function.

Some confusion about "what O.R. is" has arisen in the past due to the fact that these two different notions of optimality have not been taken into proper account. As soon as we distinguish them, the dispute about whether the "search for optimality" (e.g., Hillier and Liebermann, 1990, p. 3) is constitutive of well-understood O.R. is redundant. [/1230] It is then clear that in a systemic sense it is still a guiding, though perhaps not constitutive, idea, while in a technical sense it is better replaced by the more general concept of a search for overall preferred solutions, whereby "overall" refers to a considered problem context and a conforming combination and weighting of criteria for assessing its improvement, and "preferred" refers to a ranking of trade-offs between considered solutions (all of which will ideally be "efficient" or Pareto-optimal solutions). But of course, such a technical notion of "overall preference" as it is used in multi-criteria decision-making techniques immediately bring up issues such as "Whose preferences matter for the ranking?" and "What context matters for defining an overall perspective?" Just shifting from mathematical optimization to multi-criteria decision-making will not do, for the crucial issues reach beyond a mere question of technique. A systems-theoretical rather than just technical concept of "overall preferred" solutions will remind us of these further-reaching issues.

The Churchman-Ackoff program of research also is quite clear about another aspect of the early systems perspective of O.R. "Systems" were identified with organizational units and procedures (e.g., workflows in and between production units considered as man-machine systems) that were to be designed or redesigned systematically, with the aim of improving their functions "relative to as large a portion of a total organization as is possible" (Churchman et al, 1957, p. 6). The key issue was seen in the circumstance that due to the division of labor in organizations, each organizational unit tends to develop objectives of its own. It will, for example, try to minimize its operating cost rather than putting the organization's overall success first, over which it has no measure and control. With a view to securing overall success, well-defined and controllable unit objectives are essential, but even more essential is finding an adequate balance between unit objectives and overall objectives – an issue that Churchman and co-authors (1957, pp. 4-6) referred to as executive-type problems, as it is the key responsibility of chief executives to deal with such issues. Systems, then, were organizational or otherwise interconnected problem situations that presented executive-type problems, and O.R. accordingly was "the use of science in the study of executive-type problems" (1957, p. 6).

Science applied to systems  In retrospect, the pioneers indeed started out with a remarkably modern concept of optimality. It was a systems-theoretical rather than mathematical concept. The main concern was that good problem solving should avoid any kind of optimization that would lose sight of a whole-system perspective – the very contrary of a narrowly technical concept of optimization as it is now often associated with "classical" O.R. and with its supposedly underlying paradigm of "hard" systems thinking. If any aspect of this early systems orientation looks a bit dated today and may justly be associated with hard systems thinking, it is its tendency to hypostatize the systems concept, that is, to use it as an ontological rather than epistemological device – systems were understood to be real-world entities rather than just ways to conceive of problem contexts, as in "soft" systems thinking. However, this now usual distinction between "hard" and "soft" systems thinking did not exist at the time and in practice is never as sharp as the current O.R. and systems literature tends to depict it; for it is quite clear that all human knowledge of and thought about the "real" world refers to a conceived reality. All systems thinking therefore involves a degree of freedom as to how systems are delimited (for fuller discussion see Ulrich and Reynolds, 2010, p. 251f). Whether one relies on a rather "hard" or "soft" employment of the systems concept makes little difference in this respect. The core idea is and remains that improvement is a function of the whole relevant system and hence, that it is essential to "look at the total system" (Churchman et al, 1957, p. 56). From the outset, this effort was understood to raise fundamental questions of inquiry and ethics (e.g., Churchman, 1961 and 1971; Ackoff and Emery, 1972; Ackoff, 1974; for overviews of some central themes of Churchman and Ackoff's systems thinking, cf. Britton and McCallion, 1994; Ulrich, 2004).

There is a second aspect that looks partly dated: contemporary management and planning conceptions prefer decentralized modes of decision-making to centralized top-down planning as it might be seen to be presupposed in the pioneers' quest for a system-wide perspective. Inasmuch as this assumption was really built into the original conception of O.R., it is clear that current conceptions of O.R. need to accept the loss of a system-wide perspective that, for instance, Daellenbach and Read (1998) have described well. Methodologically speaking though, the question of how a decentralized approach can ensure a satisfactory overall result without some overall planning remains relevant. "Internal market" solutions as they are now increasingly used both in public and private sector management can to some extent replace system-wide planning and control tools, and O.R. can contribute to both approaches. The ongoing replacement in many countries of centralized governmental hospital services planning with decentralized management on the basis of so-called diagnosis-related groups (DRGs), a system of case classification and pricing that allows establishing internal markets for decentralized management as well as developing system-wide measures of performance and quality control for central management, provides an example. As this remarkable, international success story of O.R. illustrates – the DRG system was developed by the U.S. American operations researcher Robert Fetter and collaborators at Yale University [/1231] (see Fetter et al, 1980 and 1986) – a clear conception of overall results and policies is still essential, and accordingly there is still a demand for "system-wide" quantitative analysis, modeling, and control. As so often we are talking about a matter of changing emphasis rather than a genuine alternative.

In conclusion, the systems perspective of early O.R. reaches far beyond the now prevalent association of "classical" O.R. with a narrowly positivistic and "hard" understanding of systems thinking, and its tendency to equate "systems" with organizational units does not necessarily imply a focus on centralized top-down planning. Against such a distorted view, there is a need today to emphasize that O.R. was from the outset conceived as a framework of applied research that would make a difference to conventional applied science by situating problems carefully within the relevant whole systems or, as the O.R. and systems literature now prefers to put it, within their contexts. For the pioneers, this meant they had to envisage a model of applied science that did not exist at the time and which in many respects remains a challenge today – a holistic, interdisciplinary, and problem-oriented model of applied science that would be both philosophically well-grounded and practicable. It certainly helped that their notion of science was rooted in the American tradition of philosophical pragmatism rather than in the logical empiricism (or logical positivism) that was then en vogue in the scientific community, particularly in Europe. Ignoring these pragmatic rather than logical-positivist roots has often led to misunderstandings about the prominent role of the term "science" in Churchman and Ackoff's conception of O.R.; their science was not the science most readers had in mind. One of the few observers who have noted this point is Boothroyd (1978, p. 80); a summary account of the influence of pragmatism on Churchman's thinking can be found in Ulrich (2004, pp. 1125-1127; for a basic introduction to pragmatism see Ormerod, 2006; cf. my reply in Ulrich, 2016, earlier version 2007; and his comment in Ormerod, 2016). With this caveat, Churchman and Ackoff's vision for O.R. was to promote an interdisciplinary and problem-oriented science applied to systems.

Emerging difficulties and new ideas

In the 1960s and 1970s it became increasingly apparent that a basic dilemma plagued the original conception of O.R. Convincing as the idea of combining the tools of applied science and applied systems thinking was, no specifically "systemic" methods were available to make sure that problems were adequately defined in the face of complex contexts and that it was clear what good (or "preferred") "overall" solutions meant. Yet these were precisely the kind of challenges that had led the pioneers to conceive of O.R. as an applied systems discipline rather than an applied science only. They amount to basically three issues that remain relevant today:

Applied science versus applied systems thinking  There was an unresolved tension between the "systems" and "science" poles of O.R.; that is, between the insight that had spurred the birth of O.R. in the first place – that the analytical tools of science were ill-suited for capturing the reality of systems – and the continuing quest for scientific rigor that shaped the field's development, its practice, educational programs, and standards of excellence.

With hindsight, one might see O.R.'s birth defect in the circumstance that it conceived of the "systems" aspect of applied science in terms of its subject of research but not equally of its method of research. While aiming to develop an innovative, interdisciplinary and integrated kind of applied research and consultancy, the O.R. mainstream as it mirrors itself in the profession's educational programs and most respected journals (but not necessarily in good O.R. practice) largely continued to define its standards and procedures in terms of the very analytical and quantitative methods that the pioneers had found relevant but insufficient. There was a certain methodological vacuum regarding the exact nature of a "systems approach" (Churchman, 1968).

Social versus technical complexity  A second difficulty consisted in the absence of a strong foundation of operations research practice (as distinguished from O.R. techniques) in social-scientific conceptions of professional intervention such as they became available in the 1960s and 70s. Conceptions such as "planned social change" (Bennis et al, 1962), "process consultation" (Schein, 1969), "organization development" (French and Bell, 1973), and many others ("action research," "group dynamics," "sociology of knowledge," etc.) come to mind. Epistemologically speaking, what mattered more than these specific approaches is the underlying social turn of the understanding of knowledge in the applied disciplines, an idea that at the time had not yet fully liberated itself from the naturalistic tendencies of "behavioral science" but which nevertheless contained some of the seeds of the later language-analytical and discourse-theoretical revolution of contemporary philosophy (cf. Ulrich, 1988, on the theoretical implications for systems thinking and practice). Practically speaking, the main implication is a participatory reorientation of the notion of good practice in applied science, applied systems thinking, and professional intervention in general (cf. Ulrich, 2000, on the need for grounding an adequate notion of professional competence in participatory practices of civil society).

[/1232] There were some remarkable early exceptions within the field of O.R./M.S., among them Churchman and Schainblatt's (1965a, b; cf. Müller-Merbach, 1988) framework of "mutual understanding" and Boothroyd's (1978; cf. Ormerod, 2010a) process-oriented framework of "articulate intervention." Apart from such individual efforts, however, the profession's mainstream of the 1960s and 1970s hardly took up the ground-breaking concept that informed these new research approaches, the concept of the social construction of reality (Berger and Luckmann, 1966). It reaches far beyond the "behavioral science," "social psychology" and partly also "social engineering" language of the epoch. Knowledge in it is no longer understood as a function of the "real world" and proper theorizing about it only; it now also depends on what the parties involved want to be considered relevant – the normative core of what "counts" as knowledge. Furthermore, it recognizes that when it comes to inquiry and intervention in organizational and societal problem situations, and indeed in human affairs in general, the situational complexity to be understood and mastered is of a social (intersubjective) as much as a technical (functional) nature. The implication is that an adequate understanding of such situations cannot be achieved without involving those concerned – the participatory idea.

Mathematical versus contextual sophistication  Some members of the O.R. community did recognize how ground-breaking the new ideas were, for O.R. and applied systems thinking no less than for other applied disciplines. In the U.S., Churchman and Ackoff began to develop new research and training programs under the labels "social systems design" (Churchman, 1970, 1971) and "social systems science" or S3 (Ackoff, 1973, 1974, 1979b, 1981). In the U.K., Checkland (1972, 1978, 1981) set out to develop a "systems-based methodology" that might inform "systems studies" properly speaking. The result was somewhat ambivalent: separate "systems" communities formed in the U.S. and the U.K., whereas the O.R. mainstream remained largely unaffected. The O.R. community greeted the new ideas with interest – and carried on as before, without any sustained effort to review the field's foundations.

More attention was paid to the critique that Ackoff (1979a) eventually directed at the O.R. mainstream, after many years during which he and Churchman had admonished the profession to face the need for a "systems approach" that would be more socially aware and participatory in orientation. As a result of the failure to develop such an approach, Ackoff argued,

O.R. came to be identified with the use of mathematical models and algorithms rather than the ability to formulate management problems, solve them, and implement and maintain their solutions in turbulent environments. This obsession with techniques … reduced the usefulness of O.R., a reduction that was well recognized by executives who pushed it further and further down in their organizations, to where such relatively simple problems arose as permitted the application of O.R.'s mathematically sophisticated but contextually naïve techniques. (Ackoff, 1979a, p. 94, italics added).

Other strongly argued critiques were to follow, by authors such as Dando and Bennett (1981) and Rosenhead and Thunhurst (1982), but none had a similar impact. Ackoff's critique caused strong reactions for two reasons. On the one hand, it articulated the profession's longstanding failure to develop adequate frameworks for good practice and thereby apparently touched a sensitive spot; on the other hand, there was its own outrageous failure to do justice to actual O.R. practice, which had always been so much more than just applying techniques. It is this "much more" – the ways how professionals employ their tools – rather than the tools themselves which determine how contextually naive or sophisticated a profession's practice is. Ackoff's own practice demonstrated this, and so did the practice of many of his colleagues who successfully advised corporate managers and governmental authorities. They could hardly have been so successful had they relied mainly on "contextually naïve techniques."

Unfortunately, Ackoff's failure to do justice to the profession deflected attention away from the essential message. With the benefit of historical distance it stands out more clearly: ensuring a healthy balance between technical and contextual sophistication is vital to all professional practice. Technical sophistication requires specialized methods as O.R. uses them; but putting such technical sophistication to good use depends on generalist skills of recognizing and analyzing problem situations. That is, the value of technical sophistication depends on contextual sophistication. A concern for such balance should accordingly inform the development of the conceptual foundations and practical tools of O.R. as well as its educational programs and standards of good practice.

The emergence of soft and critical systems thinking

O.R. is now often defined without explicit reference to the three guiding ideas that stood at its beginnings: applied science, systems thinking, and optimum (or preferred overall) solutions. For example, it is now defined as "the discipline of applying advanced analytical methods to help make better decisions" (INFORMS, 2003). While O.R. is obviously still associated with a scientific attitude of objectivity and rigor and in this general sense remains an applied science, it is now more often seen as (abstract) technology (e.g., by Dando et al, 1977; [/1233] Boothroyd, 1978, pp. 4-6, 15f; Rosenhead, 1986; Keys, 1989, 1995; Miser, 1991; and Ormerod, 1996a, b, 2010b). Clearly though, if O.R. is an applied science (or technology) of the better, it also involves knowing what is good, that is, issues of value judgment that reach beyond science and technology.

The art of putting problems well  A change of definition does not remove the key difficulty: How do we know a problem is well put? Problem solutions are rarely better than the underlying problem definitions. If the solution isn't adequate, chances are the problem definition wasn't either. Problem definitions in turn are rarely better than the underlying understanding of problem contexts, or in more traditional systems terminology, the system's environment. If a problem definition turns out to have been inadequate, chances are the context was not adequately considered. In a world of growing interconnectedness, complexity, and diversity, understanding problem contexts well has become a crucial problem in itself. Churchman and Ackoff recognized the difficulty early on, but few recognized that they did:

There is an old saying that a problem well put is half solved. This much is obvious. What is not so obvious, however, is how to put a problem well. (Churchman et al, 1957, p. 67)

To Churchman and Ackoff, putting problems well meant to "sweep in" all aspects of the environment that might be relevant for securing improvement, rather than allowing available methods, models, and data to dictate problem definitions. Thus understood, good practice always involves some applied systems thinking, whether implicitly or explicitly. If methodological support is lacking, chances are the systems thinking involved will remain poorly defined and difficult to review.

It is thus clear why in its development since the 1970s, O.R. had to take the step from considering systems as its subject of research to also understanding systems as a way of thinking. The conceptual step involved was more fundamental than the shift from "hard" to "soft" systems thinking of which Checkland's (e.g., 1981, 1985) work immediately makes us think today; it consisted in recognizing that systems as a subject of study called for systems-based frameworks and methods to study them. Such tools for "systems studies" (Checkland) were not available in O.R. until the 1970s, no more than in other applied disciplines.

The need for systems methodologies  There was consequently a need to develop the basic idea of systemic thinking just explained – that professionals should not allow their specific methods and data alone to define the problems they deal with – into methodological principles and tools that would inform (but not replace) the use of those specific tools. Generally speaking, the more specialized a discipline becomes, the more urgent the need for such complementary methodological support will tend to be. This explains why along with O.R.'s development into an increasingly specialized mathematical discipline and, beyond it, an increasingly sophisticated profession, a new field of study emerged that focused on developing systems methodologies: new frameworks and tools were required for dealing with problems which conventional tools of science are ill-suited to deal with, the context- and perspective-dependent aspects of systems.

The 1960s and 1970s first saw the rise of "systems engineering" (originally developed at the Bell Laboratories, see Hall, 1962), "systems analysis" (developed at RAND Corporation, see Quade and Boucher, 1968), "system dynamics" (developed at MIT, see Forrester, 1961) and "managerial cybernetics" (developed at Manchester University, see Beer, 1972); but these early systems methodologies still oriented themselves so strongly toward the quantitative methods of natural science and engineering that they remained ill-suited for dealing with "socially constructed" complexity in the sense of Berger and Luckman (1966), as they could not handle conflicting contextual assumptions tied to multiple worldviews, values, and interests. A further conceptual step was required to strengthen the balance between mathematical and contextual sophistication.

The emergence of soft and critical systems methodologies  From the 1970s it gradually became clear that if systems methodologies were to be able to deal systematically with issues related to people's differing world views, values, and interests, they would require some grounding in the "interpretive" (hermeneutic) paradigm of the social sciences and the humanities, possibly also in additional traditions of thought such as critical social theory, language analysis, ethics, and philosophical pragmatism. In response to this challenge, the late 1970s and early 1980s saw the emergence of two fundamentally new approaches to systems thinking. Checkland's (1981) work in England on "soft systems methodology" (SSM) produced a practical framework for soft systems thinking. Ulrich's (1980b, 1983) work in California and later in Switzerland and England on "critical systems heuristics" (CSH) produced a practical framework for critical systems thinking, soon thereafter followed by work at Hull University in England on an overarching framework called "total systems intervention" (Jackson and Keys, 1984; Flood and Jackson, 1991; more historical detail on the two strands of CST will be given later). To be sure, Churchman (1970, 1979a, 1979b), Ackoff (1974, 1979b, [/1234] 1981) and others had prepared the ground by calling for a systems-oriented, cross-disciplinary, and participatory philosophy of management science, without however managing to translate their insights into rigorously spelled-out methodologies. Similarly, Bryer (1979), Mingers (1980), Ulrich (1981b) and Jackson (1982, 1985) subsequently called for alternatives to the work of Churchman, Ackoff, Beer, and Checkland but could not yet propose suitable methodological proposals.

It was thus left to SSM and CSH to redefine systematically what "systems thinking" means when it is informed by the hermeneutic and critical traditions of philosophy, respectively, and to translate these redefinitions of systems thinking – as an epistemology of appreciating and learning about human activity systems (Checkland) and an effort of practical reason aimed at securing reflective practice (Ulrich) – into well-defined methodological frameworks for professional intervention. In turn it was left to total systems intervention (TSI) to put these new approaches into perspective and to suggest one possible way to conceive of their complementarity. Since the latter issue comes up systematically only as a consequence of the previous proliferation of new systems methodologies, it is advisable first to focus on what was fundamentally new in the emerging "soft" and "critical" strands of systems thinking. Subsequently the two different notions of "critical" systems thinking in CSH and TSI will be analyzed in a comparative way, before the issue of an integrative framework can then be examined systematically in Part 2.

Basically, by soft systems thinking (or "interpretive" systems thinking) Checkland (1981, pp. 149f; 1983, p. 671f; 1985, p. 760; 2000, p. S15f) understood a systems approach that locates its systemic nature in the process of inquiry rather than in the real world, with a particular focus on processes of learning and problem exploration; whereas by a critical systems approach (or a "critically-normative" approach) Ulrich (1983, pp. 25, 34f, 177; 1987, p. 278f; 1988, p. 156f; 1993, p. 587f) meant the systematic use of systems thinking in the service of reflective practice, with a particular focus on the normative core of all uses of applied science and applied systems thinking. While SSM was conceived as a direct response to the limitations of systems engineering or other "hard" systems approaches in dealing with managerial and organizational problems, CSH aimed at renovating the contemporary concepts of applied science and professional intervention in general, regardless of what specific ("hard" or "soft") methodologies researchers use.

Corresponding to these aims, SSM found its theoretical inspiration mainly in Geoffrey Vickers' (1965) "appreciative" systems thinking, along with Max Weber's (1949) interpretive social science and Kurt Lewin's (1946) concept of action research, all of which can be understood to combine elements of classical sociological functionalism (Emile Durkheim, Talcott Parsons) with aspects of hermeneutic (Wilhelm Dilthey) and phenomenological (Edmund Husserl, Alfred Schütz) philosophy. By contrast, CSH found its main theoretical roots in the European (Continental) and North-American traditions of practical philosophy (or philosophy of practice), which include Kantian critical philosophy and its contemporary renaissance in critical social theory (Max Horkheimer, Jürgen Habermas, Herbert Marcuse), language analysis (John L. Austin, John R. Searle) and discourse theory (Karl-Otto Apel, Jürgen Habermas) on the one hand and American philosophical pragmatism (Charles S. Peirce, William James, John Dewey, C. West Churchman) on the other hand; major theoretical inspirations were Churchman (1971, 1979b), Habermas (1975, 1979), Kant (1781/1965), and Peirce (1878).

A core issue: "problem structuring"  Despite such differences of perspective, soft and critical systems thinking share a common interest in Churchman's question of "how to put a problem well," as a basis for understanding what competent professional intervention means. For example, it means that expert-driven problem definition, with its emphasis on analysis and objectivity, needs to be complemented with, and embedded in, a pluralistic, participation-driven, methodologically well-defined process of unfolding problems within their larger contexts and from multiple perspectives. There will often be no single, definitive definition of "the problem," as there are usually options for defining relevant contexts and perspectives – the "soft" nature of problems. These options should be made transparent not only to the professionals and decision-makers involved but to all the parties concerned, and all should be in a position to voice their concerns. Likewise, the methods professionals use to analyze a problem situation and evaluate possible solutions need to be sufficiently clear to everyone concerned to permit critical discussion of their inherent assumptions and findings. Finally, problem definitions and solutions are also to be considered "soft" in the sense that in the interest of learning, contextual assumptions should be kept open to modification and challenge, as there is no natural stopping point for declaring the process of problem structuring to be completed.

In view of this evolving understanding of good professional practice, the traditional focus on "problem solving" came increasingly to be recognized as insufficient. There was a call for systematic problem structuring, defined as "the process by which the initially presented set of conditions is translated into a set of problems, issues and questions sufficiently well defined to allow specific research action" (Woolley and Pidd, 1981, p. 197; cf. Pidd and Woolley, 1980). Problem-solving methods had to be complemented by problem-structuring methods (PSMs), [/1235] a term used by Rosenhead (1989) to describe the paradigmatic shift that would allow O.R. and systems thinking to cope with situations of complexity, uncertainty, and conflict.

It makes sense to understand both soft and critical systems methodologies as problem-structuring approaches, but a number of misunderstandings should be avoided. Soft and critical systems thinking aim to support participatory processes of problem solving and decision-making based on systematic problem structuring, rather than limiting themselves to problem structuring. PSMs, on the other hand, are now usually identified with a number of soft O.R. methods that pursue more limited objectives. With the exception of SSM, which is usually included among the PSMs, they are not based in systems thinking, social theory, and philosophy. Soft systems thinking comes into play coincidentally rather than systematically, while critical systems thinking remains altogether foreign to this "soft" concept of problem structuring. There is no intention to help develop the philosophical foundations of professional practice as rational intervention in human affairs. There is no clear distinction between methodologies (i.e., frameworks for research practice that seek to develop such foundations) and mere methods (i.e., techniques that may offer themselves for use within various frameworks but do not articulate their related assumptions). And finally, it is unclear why problem structuring should be associated with a particular "soft" paradigm of research only, and thus with the rather marginal part of O.R. called "soft O.R.," rather than being considered a constitutive element of all methodologies, whether hard, soft, or critical. Its essence consists in its heuristic, open-ended, questioning mood rather than in adherence to any particular methodological paradigm. Suffice it to refer to Polya's (1945) work on mathematical heuristics, which exemplifies a "hard" (analytical rather than hermeneutic) conception of problem structuring, and to critical systems heuristics, whose grounding in practical philosophy reaches beyond the hermeneutic tradition. Understanding problem structuring exclusively in "soft" terms is neither necessary nor conducive to developing our understanding of professional competence.

O.R. and systems thinking today

Important as the conceptual step from "problem solving" to "problem structuring" is, it does not go far enough. It lacks a philosophical basis and practical tools for dealing with the normative core of "good" professional practice. It thus risks boiling down once again to instrumentally oriented "problem solving" – a managerialist notion of good practice – without a clear conception of what it means "to put problems well" and to deal reflectively with claims to rationality, competence, and improvement. To counter this risk, critical systems thinking (CST) takes the idea of problem structuring two important steps beyond soft systems thinking.

Two key issues of critical systems thinking  The first and fundamental step consists in recognizing that all problem structuring has value implications, in the practical sense that it may do more or less justice to the different views and needs of people. There is no way round it, professional problem structuring entails choices as to what are the relevant "facts" (observations) and "values" (concerns) to be considered. What should in a specific situation constitute the basis of knowledge and values for doing a competent and rational job? There is thus a need to support professionals and decision-makers in handling this normative core of practice carefully. The challenge, in short, is dealing critically with the normative content and consequences of professional findings and conclusions.

The second step consists in recognizing that real-world complexity takes different forms and there is consequently not one best way to understand and handle it. Conversely, different intervention approaches and methods rely on different notions of social and technical complexity and accordingly have different strengths and weaknesses. There is thus a need to support professionals and decision-makers in selecting and deploying intervention approaches carefully. The challenge, in short, is dealing critically with the theoretical content and limitations of professional methods and tools.

Both issues shape the way we understand and situate problems within their contexts, which is what we mean by analyzing "problem situations" rather than "problems." By defining relevant "facts" and "values," professionals effectively define what context matters for assessing improvement. By choosing methodologies, professionals effectively define what kind of complexity matters for dealing successfully with the context. The common core issue, then, is what we might call sources of contextual selectivity. As we learned from reviewing the early systems orientation of O.R., good use of its technical sophistication depends on its contextual sophistication. Dealing carefully with both sources of contextual selectivity is therefore imperative. Yet they place rather different demands on good practice. The selectivity of methodologies regarding the nature of problem contexts can be identified theoretically once and for all, whereas the selectivity of professional findings and conclusions needs to be identified anew in each specific problem situation and therefore is basically a responsibility of practice itself.

This circumstance explains why two different strands of critical systems thinking have developed, "critical systems heuristics" (CSH) and "total systems intervention" (TSI). The core idea they share is that systems thinking is useful for handling contextual selectivity. The following definition of CST [/1236] appears to be sufficiently general to comprise the two strands yet sufficiently specific to be useful:

 

 

Definition: Critical systems thinking (CST) is an application of systems thinking that aims to support good practice in O.R. and other applied disciplines with special regard to contextual selectivity, that is, assumptions that shape the perception of problem situations. The main sources of selectivity are seen (i) in the normative content of professional findings and conclusions and (ii) in the theoretical content of professional methodologies and methods. The normative content in question resides in the "facts" and "values" considered relevant for understanding and improving problem situations; the theoretical content, in the kinds of social and technical complexity that chosen methodologies and methods can handle. Good practice regarding these two sources of selectivity raises different methodological issues and has accordingly brought forth two different strands of CST, (i) critical systems heuristics (CSH) and (ii) total systems intervention (TSI). Their shared concern, and thus the basic aim of CST in general, is to support reflective practice in handling contextual selectivity.

 

 

While this definition emphasizes the shared methodological intent and potential of the two strands of CST, it does not ignore or blur their differences. In view of these differences, the two strands of CST will now be introduced separately but following a strictly parallel structure and using the same criteria of description and assessment.

Facing the normative core of professional practice: CSH

O.R. practice, like all professional practice, entails validity claims (e.g., to relying on accurate facts, considering relevant issues, being unbiased and fostering improvement) that have practical consequences but which it cannot fully justify. Reliance on systems methodologies does not remove the difficulty, for no methodology can fully justify the answers to such inevitable questions as "Whose problem is to be solved in the first place?" and "For whom should improvement be achieved and for whom not?" What is possible, however, is a conscious and careful handling of this normative core of all professional intervention.

CST as understood in CSH  Critical systems thinking as understood in CSH begins with the idea that holistic thinking – the quest for comprehensiveness – is a meaningful effort but not a meaningful claim. Doing full and equal justice to the views and values of all the people concerned is and remains an ideal. We should not expect O.R. professionals to achieve ideals but only, to deal critically with the fact that they never do. Consequently CSH aims to assist professionals, decision-makers and stakeholders in appreciating the inevitable selectivity of the facts (observations) and values (concerns) on which depend all claims to good practice.

In practical contexts of action, selectivity tends to translate into partiality, that is, different parties will be affected differently. CSH consequently also aims to help professionals and citizens in analyzing these consequences, how different they may look if assumptions about relevant observations and concerns are modified. Good practice cannot avoid selectivity and partiality, but it can try to make the sources of selectivity transparent to all the parties concerned and to give them an opportunity to articulate their critique. It can try to examine the partiality of consequences systematically, so that decisions can be taken in full awareness of their implications for the different parties concerned. Critical systems thinking, thus understood, promotes reflective practice with respect to this normative core of professional intervention; the central idea is to support a participative process of unfolding the unavoidable selectivity and resulting partiality of professional findings and conclusions.

The methodological approach of CSH  Although systems thinking is no remedy for selectivity, it holds a key to handling it critically. Systems thinking compels us to pay attention to the systems boundaries that delimit any system of interest. We can thus understand systems thinking as a tool for reflecting about the boundaries of concern that we presuppose whenever we conceive of some problem situation in systems terms. Systems thinking then becomes a source of critique – of questioning boundary assumptions and the ways they condition validity claims – rather than, as it is more usually understood, a source of justification, that is, a way of buttressing validity claims by more comprehensive considerations of fact and value.

CSH achieves this by systematically identifying and questioning the "boundary judgments" that delimit the "reference systems" for professional findings and conclusions. Boundary judgments determine for a number of basic boundary issues and related "boundary categories" what is to be considered and what is to be left out when [/1237] it comes to defining relevant observations (judgments of fact) and concerns (judgments of value). A reference system is the set of boundary judgments that together define the context of application to which a specific claim or proposal refers and for which it is valid.

Boundary judgments are the perfect device for questioning the relevance and quality of reference systems; for unlike what one might assume at first, they define not just the scope of the context considered but equally its content, for example, how carefully we collect and formulate relevant observations and how well we argue related conjectures. This is so because any aspects of a problem situation that we fail to consider properly, say, because we argue incoherently or anticipate consequences incorrectly or fail to do justice to the concerns of others, have in fact been excluded from the relevant knowledge and value basis. Even if we do recognize some aspects as relevant and agree with others they should be considered but then fail to take them properly into account, due to lacking knowledge, to an error of judgment or some communicative misunderstanding, or because those in control of the situation decide to suppress their discussion, we have in fact (deliberately or not) excluded those aspects from our reference system. Thus the argumentative quality of a validity claim or related discussion very well reflects itself in boundary judgments (see Ulrich, 2005, p. 3).

The main device to promote such argumentative quality is critical systems discourse, a dialogical form of boundary critique. Boundary critique is a systematic process of unfolding the normative core (selectivity) of the boundary judgments that underpin any specific validity claims, so as to understand what they may mean for the parties concerned (partiality). A second basic aim is to show that there are always options for defining boundary judgments, and to allow the participants to see how different any specific claim may look in the light of such options. In cooperative settings where the parties are prepared to try and agree on their boundary judgments, these can then be modified accordingly. In controversial settings this may not be possible; boundary critique then gains a new meaning and consists in employing boundary judgments for critical purposes against those who are not prepared to disclose and question them or who even try to impose them on the basis of authority and power rather than argumentation. Boundary critique thus becomes a discursive process of challenging validity claims that take their built-in selectivity for granted.

In short, CSH understands itself as both a philosophical foundation and a practical framework for value clarification and critique. Note that "value clarification" applies to "facts" as well as to "values"; for what we take to be the knowledge basis of professional interventions (e.g., relevant data, judgments of fact, personal views, anticipated outcomes, etc.) – has no less normative implications than what we take to be its value basis (e.g., relevant concerns, notions of improvement, sources of legitimacy, ethical standards, etc.).

The methodological core principle of CSH  CSH understands the issue of selectivity as a systems-theoretical expression of the unsolved core problem of practical philosophy, the problem of practical reason: How can we justify the normative content of practice or, if we cannot, what does it mean to act rationally? Since there is no complete or objective solution, CSH reformulates the problem as the question of how we can at least achieve a "critical solution" in the sense of value clarification and critique, so that decisions can be taken in well-informed and morally conscious ways. Methodologically speaking, the question translates into the task of supporting systematic processes of boundary critique. The strategy of CSH for dealing with the problem of practical reason thus consists in what it calls the critical turn of our notion of rational practice – practice is rational to the extent it is aware of its inbuilt selectivity and partiality and qualifies its claims accordingly. This is how CSH aims to support the quest for rational practice despite its unavoidable selectivity and partiality.

Accordingly, CSH's methodological core principle is the principle of boundary critique: what a claim means and how valid it is depends on its reference system, that is, the boundary judgments that inform its view of relevant fact and values and thus its empirical and normative selectivity. To appreciate and qualify the adequacy of professional findings and conclusions it is consequently indispensable to examine the underpinning boundary judgments.

To this end, CSH proposes twelve generic boundary categories (see Figure 1). They stand for four crucial sources of selectivity built into all practice: its sources of motivation, of power, of knowledge and of legitimation. Each boundary category translates into two boundary questions, one asking what is the case ("is" mapping) and the other what should be the case ("ought" mapping). This [/1238] yields a checklist of boundary questions that explicitly define the precise intent of each boundary category (see Ulrich, 1987, 1996, 2000; Ulrich and Reynolds, 2010). They can be used, first, to identify boundary judgments systematically; second, to examine claims in the light of alternative boundary judgments; and third, as mentioned before, to challenge claims that rely on boundary judgments they take for granted.

 

July 2016

Su
Mo
Tu
We
Th
Fr
Sa
 
 
  
  
 
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
 
 
 
 
 
 

August 2016

Su
Mo
Tu
We
Th
Fr
Sa
 
1
2
 3
 4
 5
 6
 7
 8
 9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 

 

 

Figure 1: CSH boundary categories

Copyleft  copy left  1983 W. Ulrich

Fig. 1: Boundary categories of critical systems heuristics
(Source: adapted from Ulrich, 1983, p. 258)

 

The last-mentioned application leads to an argumentative employment of boundary judgments known as "polemical" or "emancipatory" boundary critique. It creates an improved symmetry of critical competence among the parties concerned whatever special knowledge or expertise they may have concerning the problem at issue. It constitutes an important methodological backing of the earlier-explained critical turn of the quest for rational practice. As a practicable model of cogent argumentation about normative issues (see Ulrich, 1983, pp. 301-310; 1993, pp. 599-605; and 2000, pp. 257-260), it may be understood to pragmatize Habermas' (1979, 1984, 1990) theoretical model of rational practical discourse. The latter's ideal nature has confined his well-known "discourse ethics" to remaining a much-discussed theory rather than a practicable model of moral discourse, so there is indeed a pressing need for pragmatization.

In sum, CSH can be defined as a methodological framework for boundary critique aimed at supporting a critical solution to the unsolved problem of practical reason. Despite its emancipatory implications – the aspect for which it is best known – CSH should not be misunderstood and used as an emancipatory systems approach only. The principle of boundary critique is vital for all rational practice, whatever importance is attached to emancipatory issues. Accordingly CSH does not aim to be a self-contained systems methodology but is better understood as a reflective framework that makes sense whatever specific methodology is used.

Practical implementation: the main procedure of CSH  Boundary critique is best implemented as an iterative process of reflecting on, and discussing, the implications of alternative boundary judgments. When we change some boundary judgement, the reference system of which it is constitutive will change, too; consequently, all other boundary judgments may need being reconsidered and adapted. CSH captures this idea and its methodological consequences with the image of an "eternal triangle" of boundary judgments, value judgments, and judgments of fact, an idea that will be taken up in Part 2. Given that iterative processes are not easy to teach and to learn, it may help those new to boundary critique more at this stage to suggest a standard sequence for unfolding the boundary categories and questions of CSH (see Figure 2).

 

CSH unfolding sequence for boundary critique

Copyleft  copy left  2007, 2010 W. Ulrich, M. Reynolds

Fig. 2: A standard sequence of boundary critique
(Source: adapted from Ulrich and Reynolds, 2010, p. 259, and Reynolds, 2007, p. 106)

 

Recent development  In an effort to strengthen its applicability and relevance to good professional practice, the ongoing development of CSH currently aims to tie its central concept of boundary critique closer to a pragmatic framework of critical and responsible argumentation called critical pragmatism (Ulrich, 2006, 2007). Some aspects of this current effort will be taken up in Part 2.

Ensuring informed methodology choice: TSI/CH

Good professional practice depends on the proper choice and use of intervention methodologies and conforming methods. Applied systems thinking can support professionals in adapting their methodologies and methods to the organizational or societal problem contexts in question. Good systems practice will take advantage of the availability of different systems methodologies that, because they are informed by different methodological paradigms, can do justice to different kinds of contexts; it is in this sense multi-paradigmatic.

TSI emerged from a research program on this issue initiated by M.C. Jackson in cooperation with P. Keys at the University of Hull in 1983 and subsequently continued with R.L. Flood till the early 1990s. The ideas that led to [/1239] TSI can be traced in Jackson and Keys (1984, 1987), Keys (1987), and Jackson (1982, 1985, 1987a, b, 1990, 1991); the main text is Flood and Jackson (1991). Useful for reviewing more recent developments are Jackson (1997, 1999, 2000, 2003, 2006a, b); a brief history of ideas from TSI's perspective can be found in Jackson (2000, p. 357f). Jackson (2003, 2006b) meanwhile refers to his development of TSI as "creative holism" (subsequently: CH, not to be confused with CSH) or "critical systems practice"; I will not adopt the latter label, for I have used it throughout my writings (e.g., Ulrich, 1996, p. 45f; 2003, p. 325) to refer to reflective practice of systems methodologies in general.

Both TSI and CH (subsequently: TSI/CH) assume that the nature of problem contexts can usefully be captured in terms of alternative sociological paradigms for describing the social reality in question (see Burrell and Morgan, 1979) along with various organizational "images" or systems metaphors of organizational theory (see Morgan, 1986). Systems methodologies, depending on the kinds of problem contexts for which they have been developed, may themselves be characterized in such terms, and their strengths and weaknesses can thus be better understood. It thus becomes possible to match contexts and methodologies in a systematic way, so as to support professionals in choosing the methodologies and conforming methods best suited to deal with a situation. As Jackson recalls:

To explore and develop this idea, Paul Keys and I, during 1983/84, initiated a research program, at the University of Hull, aimed theoretically at explaining the relationships between different systems-based methodologies and practically at discovering the efficacy of particular approaches in various problem contexts. (Jackson, 2000, p. 357f; similarly 2010, p. 134)

CST as understood in TSI/CH  CST as understood in TSI/CH begins with the idea that applied systems thinking – the attempt to understand entire problem contexts in systems terms – is meaningful to the extent we are aware of the sociological paradigms and organizational metaphors that inform it. By relying on different paradigms and metaphors, different systems methodologies make different theoretical assumptions about the nature of problem contexts. Applied systems thinking accordingly depends for its justification and rationality on paradigmatic fit between systems methodologies and problem context.

In O.R. and other forms of applied research, the requirement of paradigmatic fit translates into a need for informing the selection and use of methodologies and conforming methods by paradigm analysis as well as, where relevant, metaphor analysis. TSI/CH consequently puts the critical focus on the theoretical underpinnings of alternative research paradigms rather than, as does CSH, on the normative core of professional practice. CST, thus understood, promotes reflective practice with respect to these theoretical underpinnings; the central idea is to support a theoretically informed process of matching methodologies with problem contexts.

The methodological approach of TSI/CH  The main theoretical device of TSI/CH is a contingency approach to methodology choice, based on a paradigmatic and to a lesser degree also a metaphorical analysis of the three major traditions of systems thinking thus far – hard, soft, and critical systems thinking. The idea is that there is no such thing as a best systems methodology and underpinning tradition of systems thinking; rather, situational aspects of the problem context at hand determine what tradition of systems thinking is best suited as a source of methodological guidance and specific methods or tools of intervention. A second idea is that such an approach promises to resolve the "O.R. in crisis" debate of the 1970s and 1980s, as it offers a way to see "hard" and "soft" O.R. approaches as appropriate for dealing with different problem contexts rather than competing for the same ones.

Contingency frameworks are also called contingency theories, as they involve theoretical generalizations about the crucial aspects of the application domain to which the framework is to be applied. This theoretical device is often used in the social sciences (e.g., in management and organization theories) when a variety of approaches is required to handle a given class of problems, as the proper approach is dependent ("contingent") on the situation or, more precisely, on a range of changing situations.

Applied to contexts of professional intervention, using a contingency approach implies that it is possible empirically to identify some independent (contextual) variables that regularly, for reasons that can be explained theoretically, may be expected to condition the outcome of interventions. Subject to this condition, a contingency approach can be called a contingency theory and can be assumed to explain and justify the selection of situation-specific intervention approaches. It follows that the crucial question for a contingency approach is whether it can identify and validate a small number of empirical dimensions (ideally only two) in terms of which both intervention contexts and intervention approaches can be classified in a relevant and reliable way.

In short, TSI/CH understands itself as a contingency theory for methodology reflection and selection that bases its classification of intervention situations and approaches on the two main tools of paradigm analysis and metaphor analysis.

The methodological core principle of TSI/CH  TSI/CH understands the issue of selectivity as a question of the (social-) theoretical assumptions that inform the "matching" of intervention approaches and problem [/1240] contexts: How can we ensure "paradigmatic fit" of the systems methodologies and situations we employ? Methodologically speaking, the question translates into the task of developing and validating a classification of systems methodologies that can be mapped onto a corresponding classification or problem contexts. This is what TSI/CH calls a system of systems methodologies (SOSM). It says that systems methodologies and conforming methods are well chosen if their underlying systems metaphor (machine, organism, etc.) and/or paradigm (functionalist, interpretive, etc.) match with the kind of complexity or "complications" (Jackson and Keys, 1984, p. 474) that a problem context entails. The complications in question are captured in terms of two dimensions, the "systems" dimension and the "participants" dimension, which in the terms of the present paper stand for the two interdependent core issues of complexity (the number, interconnectedness, and dynamic nature of the aspects to be considered) and diversity (the number, divergence, and importance of multiple perspectives). Table 1 summarizes the extended SOSM of 1991.

 

Table 1: The extended system of systems methodologies (SOSM)

(Source: adapted from Flood & Jackson, 1991, p. 42; Jackson, 1991, pp. 29, 31; 2000, p. 359)

 

 

 

Participants dimension of contexts
(increasing diversity of values)

Unitary

(functional
paradigm)

Hard systems
thinking

Pluralist

(interpretive
paradigm)

Soft systems
thinking

Coercive

(emancipatory
paradigm)

Emancipatory
systems thinking

Systems
dimension
of contexts
(increasing complexity)

S
i
m
p
l
e

Simple-unitary problem contexts
(systems metaphor:
machine)

· Operations research (O.R.)

· Systems engineering (SE)

· Systems analysis (SA)

Simple-pluralist problem contexts
(systems metaphors:
culture, coalition)

· Systems approach
(Churchman)

· Strategic assumption surfacing and testing (SAST)

Simple-coercive problem contexts
(systems metaphor:
prison)

· Critical systems
heuristics (CSH)

C
o
m
p
l
e
x

Complex-unitary problem contexts
(systems metaphors: organism, brain)

· Organizational
cybernetics/
viable systems diagnosis (VSD)

· Socio-technical
systems thinking

Complex-pluralist problem contexts
(systems metaphors: culture, coalition)

· Interactive planning
(Ackoff)

· Soft systems
methodology (SSM)

Complex-coercive problem contexts
(systems metaphor: prison)

· ?

Copyleft  copy left  2010 W. Ulrich

 

The original, four-celled version of the SOSM (Jackson and Keys, 1984) distinguished "hard" and "soft" methodologies only. Although it is frequently cited as the origin of the TSI strand of CST, it actually did not yet introduce the notion of "critical" systems thinking and offered no place to CSH. When CSH became known to the authors after publishing their 1984 work, integrating its notion of a "critical systems approach" was not easy and took some time. First hints at the planned extension of the SOSM appeared in some articles of the late 1980s (e.g., Jackson, 1987a, b, 1990), but the extended SOSM was presented only in 1991 (Flood and Jackson, 1991; Jackson, 1991).

With a view to the integrated perspective at which the current paper aims, the difficulties in question are worth explaining. We have seen that CSH aims to support the use of all methodologies and methods, whether they are based on a hard or soft or non-systemic paradigm – CSH's way of being multi-paradigmatic. We have also seen that CSH does not aim to be employed as a self-contained methodology. Moreover, its understanding of reflective practice aims at the "other," practical-normative, dimension of reason – the unsolved problem of practical reason – of which the SOSM with its focus on theoretical paradigms has no grasp. For CSH, justification of practice is a matter of practice itself, as no reference to theory (much less to paradigm choice) can justify its normative core; accordingly it aims at "critical heuristics of social practice" rather than "critical theory of society" or any other kind of social theory (including contingency theory). All these aims cut across the different problem-solving contexts and paradigms considered in the SOSM. The SOSM, by contrast, assumes that any methodology can be assigned to a specific type of problem context; that doing so is a matter of theory (paradigm analysis) rather than of practice itself; and that any methodology thus classified is then to be employed as a "dominant" (if not stand-alone) approach whenever its inbuilt paradigm matches the requirements of the context.

The only way CSH could apparently be adjusted to the logic of the SOSM was by narrowing its notion of critical systems thinking down to a merely "emancipatory" purpose, as distinguished from the overall "critical" purpose of the SOSM. This was achieved by associating it with a "prison" metaphor that supposedly made it adequate for "coercive" problem [/1241] contexts only. CSH could thus be integrated into the SOSM, but at the expense of treating it as a self-contained methodology that seemingly was to be chosen (or not) as an alternative to soft and hard systems methodologies. As a result, its concern for the normative core of all practice moved out of sight (for critical discussion and alternatives, see Ulrich, 2003).

In British O.R., CSH was henceforth understood mainly through the lens of the SOSM, and "critical systems thinking" became widely identified with TSI. Consequently, CST was now almost the same as the SOSM – an extended contingency framework for methodology choice that also offered itself as a framework for discussing the evolution of O.R. (e.g., Jackson, 2006a). Both uses attracted much interest and the mentioned difficulties of the extended SOSM did not hamper its success in helping to raise awareness in the profession that there are options for conceiving of good professional practice. The discussion that the SOSM was able to generate in turn has helped to make CSH more known, so that its core principle of boundary critique is increasingly being recognized as an important, independent source of critical thought on practice. These diverse successes of the SOSM certainly have contributed to the comparatively high level of methodological awareness and discussion that distinguishes the O.R. profession, which in turn has allowed it to bring forth soft and critical systems ideas that are now radiating into many other fields.

It is another question whether the SOSM's specific assignment of systems methodologies to problem contexts is theoretically well-founded and effectively conducive to good (i.e., sufficiently reflective) practice. Suffice it to say that some doubts have arisen in the debate as to whether its theoretical basis (i.e., in essence, its two dimensions for mapping problem contexts) is strong enough to warrant such "pigeon-holing" of systems methodologies or even a claim to offering the only valid view of their nature and complementarity. Other methodologies (including CSH) might just as well assign a limited rather than overarching role to the SOSM and to the TSI framework built around it, thus pigeon-holing TSI/CH within their frameworks of good O.R. practice. In any case, the integrated perspective at which the present effort aims renders such mutual pigeon-holing rather pointless and we therefore need not discuss the issue in any detail. The multi-paradigm and multi-methodology orientation of TSI/CH is meaningful for reflective practice without any presumption of defining the only adequate classification and use of systems methodologies.

Practical implementation: the main procedure of TSI/CH  To support methodology choice in practice, the SOSM still needed to be embedded in a methodology properly speaking, that is, a framework that would guide practitioners in asking relevant questions and proceeding systematically. This is what "total systems intervention" (TSI), a name adopted in 1991, is all about. It stands for the practical procedure of methodology choice and implementation that Flood and Jackson (1991; also Jackson, 1991) proposed on the basis of the SOSM as a "meta-methodology" for critical systems practice. The procedure may be employed in a linear or iterative way. To its original three phases labelled "creativity," "choice," and "implementation," Jackson's (2003, 2006b) revision of TSI as "creative holism" (CH) has more recently added a fourth phase, "Reflection" (see Table 2).

 

Table 2: The meta-methodology of TSI/CH:
standard phases of methodology choice and use

(Source: adapted from Flood and Jackson, 1991, p. 54; Jackson, 1991, p. 276;
2000, p. 372; and 2006b, p. 654)

Phase

Activity / aim

(1)
CREATIVITY

Task
Tools
Outcome

 

To identify major aims and issues of problem context
Use of different metaphors and paradigms to gain different perspectives
Appreciation of dominant and dependent metaphors/paradigms and related issues

(2)

CHOICE

Task
Tools
Outcome

 

To choose appropriate systems methodologies and methods
Use of SOSM to reveal strengths/weaknesses of methodologies and methods
Choice of dominant and dependent systems methodologies and methods

(3)
IMPLEMENTATION

Task
Tools
Outcome

 

To arrive and implement specific positive change proposals
Systems methodologies/methods used properly according to SOSM
Relevant change according to the concerns of the different paradigms

(4)
REFLECTION

Task
Tools
Outcome

 

To evaluate the intervention and ensure methodological learning
Understanding of the concerns of different paradigms regarding good practice
Methodological progress

Copyleft  copy left  2010 W. Ulrich

 

The creativity phase is to encourage consideration of what alternative systems paradigms and root metaphors might mean for thinking about a problem context at hand, so that a "dominant" metaphor can be identified and it becomes clear whether preference should be given to a hard (mainly functionalist), soft (mainly interpretive), or critical (mainly emancipatory) orientation. In the choice and [/1242] implementation phases, a conforming particular systems methodology can then be chosen based on the SOSM and used to implement specific change proposals. In the reflection phase, finally, outcomes of TSI/CH guided intervention are to be reflected so that methodological learning can take place.

The new reflection phase brings Jackson's "creative holism" (CH) a bit closer to CSH's focus on reflective practice. It widens the focus from theoretical justification ex ante to ongoing reflection based on practice and taking place in practice. Not unlike the "critical reflection mode" that Flood (1995, p. 227f) previously added to TSI, CH's "reflection" phase aims to evaluate, "after the event" (Jackson, 2003, p. 289), how TSI/CH has been used in specific interventions, with a view to improving TSI/CH itself. Although the underlying notions of learning and rationality may still not be "practical" in the philosophical sense in which CSH understands the term – in the sense of recognizing practical reason as a genuine and indispensable dimension of rational practice – the reflection phase nevertheless promises new chances for cooperation between TSI/CH and CSH. For example, given that it is not entirely clear how exactly the TSI/CH framework should be employed to evaluate its own application, CSH might be able to support CH's reflection phase; the latter would then be properly employed for reflective ends across systems paradigms and frameworks, addressing the practical-normative no less than the theoretical-instrumental dimensions of reason.

Recent development  Another recent development brings CH considerably closer to sharing its understanding of CST and of reflective practice with CSH: it has now abandoned TSI's claim to "meta-paradigmatic" status in favor of multi-paradigmatic "critique between the paradigms" (Jackson, 2010, p. 136). This is also more consistent with a concern for pluralism as CSH understands it, in the words of Churchman (1968, p. 231): "The systems approach begins when first you see the world through the eyes of another."

Consequently CH also no longer insists on choosing a single "dominant" methodological paradigm, which in practice meant that there was virtually no room for CSH ever to guide an intervention (Flood, 1995, describes nine cases employing TSI of which only one was based on CSH). Following much discussion about the value of methodological "complementarism" or "pluralism" (e.g., Jackson, 1999), "mixing methods" (e.g., Midgley, 1997), and "multi-methodology" (e.g., Mingers and Gill, 1997), a free combination or "mixing" of methodologies or parts of methodologies and conforming methods is now encouraged. This again brings TSI/CH a bit closer to CSH, which is premised on the idea that essential for the quality of professional practice "is not which type of method(s) we use but rather what validity claims we associate with the methods we use and how critically we deal with these claims" (cf. Ulrich, 2003, p. 337f). This modification also makes CH more flexible to use and thus brings it closer to the needs of practice. It can now be said to help practitioners "harness the various systems methodologies, methods and models" by being "multi-paradigm, multi- methodology, and multi-method in orientation" (Jackson, 2006b, pp. 248 and 253; 2010, p. 136). This makes it a less pressing issue whether TSI/CH can really claim to be a contingency theory, that is, whether its classification of methodologies and problem contexts is social-theoretically well-founded and practically adequate.

These developments suggest that the two strands of CST might still find ways to live with one another, or at least to encourage practitioners to combine whatever tools of critical reflection and discourse they find relevant in both strands, so as to enhance their professional competence and practice. After all, that is the core idea of critical systems thinking.

A summary comparison of CSH and TSI/CH

To facilitate an overview of the discussed aspects of CST, Table 3 summarizes the accounts of CSH and TSI/CH in a way that should facilitate comparison. In addition, Table 4 summarizes a few additional aspects that reach beyond the present discussion, concerning the evaluation, mutual perception, and possible developments of the two strands of CST.

 

Table 3: CSH and TSI compared: discussed aspects

(Source: adapted from Ulrich, 2012a, p. 1243, and 2013, p. 324)

Aspect

CSH

TSI/CH

Core idea

Professional practice involves validity claims that cannot be justified theoretically but at least can be handled openly and critically by practice itself

Professional practice involves methodological choices that can be justified theoretically by analyzing underpinning research paradigms and systems metaphors

Basic aim

Reflective practice with respect to the normative and empirical content of professional findings & conclusions

Reflective practice with respect to the theoretical content of (systems) methodologies and methods

Critical focus

Analysis of reference systems: surfacing the boundary judgements constitutive of the facts and values considered relevant, and analyzing how they condition different perceptions of practical claims (e.g., problem definitions, proper ends and means, proposals for action or evaluation standards)

Paradigm analysis: surfacing the theoretical paradigms and metaphors underpinning alternative methodologies and analyzing how they condition different perceptions of the nature of problem contexts and suitable methodologies (e.g., functionalist, interpretive, emancipatory or post-modern perspectives)

Basic approach

Critical systems discourse: a discursive framework for value clarification and critique

Contingency theory: a contingency framework for methodology choice and use

Methodological
core principle

Boundary critique: unfolding the selectivity of reference systems

Informed methodology choice: matching systems methodologies with problem contexts

Main critical
device

Checklist of boundary questions: a definition of boundary categories for "is" and "ought" mapping (i.e., descriptive and normative analysis) of reference systems

System of systems methodologies (SOSM): a classification of problem contexts and conforming systems methodologies

Implementation

A discursive process of unfolding selectivity: a standard sequence of boundary critique

A holistic meta-methodology of methodology choice and use: standard phases of context and methodology matching

Copyleft  copy left  2012 W. Ulrich

 

 

Table 4: CSH and TSI compared: some further, evaluative aspects

(Source: adapted from Ulrich, 2012a, p. 1244)

Aspect

CSH

TSI/CH

Major achievement

Critical holism, or the "critical turn" of applied systems thinking: from a holistic to a critically-normative understanding of the systems idea – systems thinking as a form of critique

Creative holism, or the "multi-methodological" turn of applied systems thinking: from mono- to multi-paradigmatic systems practice – systems thinking as a form of multi-methodology, multi-method, and multi-paradigm practice

Mutual perception and critique

CSH about TSI/CH: "TSI/CH may not be a particularly good example of CST, as it achieves little in the way of supporting systematic value clarification and critique with respect to the contextual assumptions and consequences that all professional practice implies, whatever methodologies and methods it may rely on. Reflective practice cannot be replaced by, or reduced to, a theoretical critique of methodology choice based mainly on paradigm analysis"

TSI/CH about CSH: "CSH may not be a particularly good example of CST, as it achieves little in the way of supporting systematic paradigm analysis and critique with respect to the contextual assumptions that all methodology choice implies, whatever views and values the people concerned may have. Theoretical critique of methodology choice cannot be replaced by, or reduced to, reflective practice based mainly on boundary critique"

 

"Boundary critique is more fundamental than paradigm analysis, for our boundaries of concern tend to determine how we see paradigms"

"Paradigm analysis is more fundamental than boundary critique, for our paradigms tend to determine how we see boundaries"

 

"TSI pigeon-holes CSH by reducing its use to coercive problem contexts, against its broader aim of supporting reflective practice in all kinds of problem contexts (i.e., regardless of the methodologies and paradigms employed)"

"CSH pigeon-holes TSI by reducing its use to theoretically informed methodology choice and mixing, against its broader aim of supporting reflective practice in all (i.e., not only theoretical) respects"

Some strengths (+),
difficulties (-),
and future challenges (?)

(+) Translates the problem of holism into a framework for reflective professional practice

(+) Provides a basis for debate about the historical development of O.R. and applied systems thinking

(+) Provides a basis for dealing with the practical-normative as well as the theoretical-instrumental dimension of rational practice

(+) Provides a framework for multi- methodology, multi-method, multi-paradigm professional practice

 

(+) Supports reflective practice of other methodologies and methods rather than claiming to be a self-contained methodology

(+) Supports the theoretical understanding of other methodologies rather than being a methodology itself

 

(+) Encourages a dialogical and practical-normative, rather than merely expert-driven and theoretically based, notion of professional competence

(+) Encourages paradigmatic and methodological awareness and openness as aspects of professional competence

 

(-) Theoretical grounding in practical philosophy demands some interest in basic philosophical reasoning

(-) Theoretical grounding in sociological paradigms demands some interest in social theory

 

(-) Practice requires discursive skills

(-) Practice requires mastery of a multitude of systems methodologies and methods

 

(-) Didactic aspect to be developed: How can ordinary professionals, decision-makers, and citizens acquire the new critical competence that boundary critique promises?

(-) Didactic aspect to be developed: How can practitioners themselves, rather than just pre-defined contingency theory, be put in charge of methodology selection?

 

(?) Can the vision of a "critically-heuristic training for citizens" be realized?

(?) Can the missing normative dimension of rational practice be brought in?

Copyleft  copy left  2012 W. Ulrich

 

 Summary and conclusions for Part 1

What has CST to contribute to good O.R. practice, and how can its two main strands, CSH and TSI, work together in a mutually supportive way? This two-part essay seeks to give new answers to these two questions. The present first part prepares the ground by correcting several misconceptions that have hampered their discussion in the past, and allows the following conclusions:

1. Counter to what is usually assumed, O.R.'s early understanding of good practice started out with a systems-theoretical concept of optimality that reached far beyond the concept of mathematical optimization with which "classical" O.R. is now often associated and which has led to its characterization as "hard" systems thinking.

2. Owing to the fact that to this day, no coherent overall account of CST is available that would do justice to both its strands, its potential for contributing to good O.R. practice is now usually underestimated, as it is either ignored or else identified with only one of the two strands. Since the prevalent perception, particularly in Britain, tends to identify CST mainly with TSI's [/1243] focus on theoretically informed methodology choice and mixing, its underpinning notion of reflective (or "critical") practice appears to be mainly a matter of social theorizing remote from practice, whereas the genuinely practical dimension and normative core of rational practice have moved out of sight.

3. As a consequence of the two previous points, the development of O.R. has come to be seen as a seemingly linear evolution from "hard" (classical O.R.) to "soft" (SSM) and "critical" (CST) approaches. Such a perspective is not conducive to promoting good O.R. practice, nor does it justice to its actual richness.

4. Finally, as a consequence of all three previous points, the discussion about CST has remained largely an insider discussion. Accounts of its two strands, CSH and TSI, have remained mainly partisan accounts and their mutual relationship has not become clear; accordingly unclear and marginal has their contribution to O.R. practice remained.

In response to these observations, a view of O.R. as applied systems thinking emerges that sees systems thinking as constitutive for good O.R. practice in general, rather than only for certain recent developments and/or marginal applications (such as "soft O.R.," "community O.R." or "critical management science"). An essential element of this new view is reflective practice. Another essential element, related to it, is the quest for increasing O.R.'s sophistication with regard to context analysis. Just as O.R.'s early concept of optimality (or "optimal solution") included the idea of mathematical optimization but went beyond it, a contemporary concept of good O.R. practice might once again try to strike a balance between the demands of technical and contextual sophistication; for the practical value of O.R.'s technical sophistication depends on its contextual sophistication.

In such a recovered view of O.R. as applied systems thinking, CST has a basic role to play: it responds to the deficits of practicability that the original quest for overall "whole-systems" rationality entailed, by shifting the focus from the original, hopeless attempt of avoiding contextual selectivity to its transparent and systematic handling. Therein resides the basic idea and value of "critical" systems thinking: it can support reflective practice with special regard to contextual selectivity, across all strands of systems thinking and contexts of professional intervention. [/1244]

It is clear, then, that CST should be seen as an integrated part of O.R. methodology, rather than as a (final?) stage of its evolution. It also follows that CST is not well understood and practiced as a self-contained systems paradigm and/or methodology. Furthermore, what holds true for CST as a whole also holds true for its two strands: they need to be situated systematically within an integrated framework of reflective practice rather than seen as self- contained methodologies. Accordingly important it is to work towards a coherent account of the ways in which together they can support reflective practice.

With these objectives in mind, the present first part of this essay, for the first time in the history of CST, has undertaken a comparative, non-partisan account of the key ideas of its two strands. As a result, not only their different notions of reflective practice have become clearer but also their shared characteristics: there emerges a shared potential of the two strands of CST to enhance O.R.'s [/1245] contextual sophistication in a mutually supportive way, and thereby to contribute to O.R. as reflective practice of applied systems thinking. In an effort to tap this potential, the second part will take the idea of an "integrated" conception of O.R. and critical systems thinking one crucial step further, by embedding it in a new conception of good professional practice as argumentative practice and by situating the role of both strands of CST within it.

(To be continued)

 

References

Ackoff R.L. (1973). Science in the systems age: beyond IE, O.R., and M.S. Opns. Res. 21: 661-671.

Ackoff R.L. (1974). Redesigning the Future: A Systems Approach to Societal Problems. Wiley: New York.

Ackoff R.L (1979a). The future of operational research is past. J. Opl. Res. Soc. 30: 93-104.

Ackoff R.L. (1979b). Resurrecting the future of operational research. J. Opl. Res. Soc. 30: 189-199.

Ackoff R.L. (1981). Creating the Corporate Future. Wiley: New York.

Ackoff R.L. and Emery F.E. (1972). On Purposeful Systems. Tavistock Publications

Ackoff R.L. and Sasieni M.W. (1968). Fundamentals of Operations Research. Wiley: New York.

Beer S. (1959). What has cybernetics to do with operational research? Opl. Res. Quart. (now J. Opl. Res. Soc.) 10: 1-21.

Beer S. (1972). Brain of the Firm: The Managerial Cybernetics of Organization. Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin (2nd. edn., Wiley: Chichester, UK, 1981).

Bennis W.G., Benne K.D., and Chin R. (eds.) (1962). The Planning of Change: Readings in the Applied Behavioral Sciences. Holt, Rinehard & Winston: New York.

Berger P.L. and Luckmann T. (1966). The Social Construction of Reality: A Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge. Doubleday: Garden City, NY.

Boothroyd H. (1978). Articulate Intervention: The Interface of Science, Mathematics and Administration. Taylor & Francis: London.

Britton G.A. and McCallion H. (1994). An overview of the Singer/Churchman/Ackoff school of thought. Syst Pract 7: 487-521.

Bryer R.A. (1979). The status of the systems approach. Omega 7: 219-231.

Burrell G. and Morgan G. (1979). Sociological Paradigms and Organizational Analysis: Elements of the Sociology of Corporate Life. Heinemann: London.

Checkland P. (1972). Towards a systems-based methodology for real-world problem solving. J. Syst. Eng. 3: 1-30.

Checkland P. (1978). The origins and nature of "hard" systems thinking. J. Appl. Syst. Anal. 5: 99-110.

Checkland P. (1981). Systems Thinking, Systems Practice. Wiley: Chichester, UK.

Checkland P. (1983). OR and the systems movement: mappings and conflicts. J. Opl. Res. Soc. 34: 661-675.

Checkland P. (1985). From optimizing to learning: a development of systems thinking for the 1990s. J. Opl. Res. Soc. 36: 757-767.

Checkland P. (2000). Soft systems methodology: a thirty year retrospective. Syst. Res. 17 (Special issue, Nov): S11-S58.

Churchman C.W. (1961). Prediction and Optimal Decision: Philosophical Issues of a Science of Values. Prentice- Hall: Englewood Cliffs, NJ.

Churchman C.W. (1968). The Systems Approach. Dell: New York.

Churchman C.W. (1970). Operations research as a profession. Mngt. Sci. 17: B37-B53.

Churchman C.W. (1971). The Design of Inquiring Systems: Basic Concepts of Systems and Organization. Basic Books: New York.

Churchman C.W. (1979a). Paradise regained: a hope for the future of systems design education. In: Bayraktar B.A., Muller-Merbach H., Roberts J.E. and Simpson M.G. (eds.). Education in Systems Science. Taylor & Francis: London, pp. 17-22.

Churchman C.W. (1979b). The Systems Approach and Its Enemies. Basic Books: New York.

Churchman C.W., Ackoff R.L., and Arnoff E.L. (1957). Introduction to Operations Research. Wiley: New York, and Chapman & Hall: London.

Churchman C.W. and Schainblatt A.H. (1965a). The researcher and the manager: a dialectic of implementation. Mngt. Sci. 11: B69-B87.

Churchman C.W. and Schainblatt A.H. (1965b). On mutual understanding. Mngt. Sci. 12: B40–B42.

Churchman C.W. and Ulrich W. (1980). The status of the systems approach: reply to Bryer. Omega 8: 277-280.

Daellenbach H.G. and Read E.G. (1998). Success and survival of OR groups – where to from here? J. Opl. Res. Soc. 49: 430-433.

Dando M.R. and Bennett P.G. (1981). A Kuhnian crisis in management science? J. Opl. Res. Soc. 32: 91–103.

Dando M.R., Defrenne A., and Sharp R.G. (1977). Could O.R. be a science? Omega 5: 89-92.

Fetter R.B., Shin Y., Freeman J.L., Averill R.F., and Thompson J.D. (1980). Case-mix definition by diagnosis-related groups. Medical Care 18(2): entire Supplement 2, 1–53.

Fetter R.B. and Freeman J.L. (1986). Diagnosis related groups: product line management within hospitals. Acad. Mngt. Rev. 11: 41-54.

Flood R.L. and Jackson M.C. (1991). Creative Problem Solving: Total Systems Intervention. Wiley: Chichester, UK.

Flood R.L. (1995). Solving Problem Solving: A Potent Force for Effective Management. Wiley: Chichester, UK.

Forrester J.W. (1961). Industrial Dynamics. MIT Press: Cambridge, MA.

French W.L. and Bell C. (1973). Organization Development: Behavioral Science Interventions for Organization Improvement, 2nd. edn., Prentice-Hall: Englewood Cliffs, NJ.

Habermas J. (1975). Legitimation Crisis. Beacon Press: Boston, MA.

Habermas J. (1979). Communication and the Evolution of Society. Beacon Press: Boston, and Heinemann, London..

Habermas J. (1984). The Theory of Communicative Action, Vol. 1: Reason and the Rationalization of Society. Polity Press: Cambridge, UK.

Habermas J. (1990). Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action. Polity Press: Cambridge, UK.

Hall A.D. (1962). A Methodology for Systems Engineering. Van Nostrand: Princeton, NJ.

Hillier F.S. and Lieberman G.J. (1990). Introduction to Operations Research. McGraw-Hill: New York.

INFORMS (2003) What operations research is. Operations Research: The Science of the Better, Web site of the Institute for Operations Research and the Management Sciences,
http://www.scienceofbetter.org/what/index.htm.

Jackson M.C. (1982). The nature of soft systems thinking: the work of Churchman, Ackoff and Checkland. J. Appl. Syst. Anal. 9: 17-29. [/1246]

Jackson M.C. (1985). Social systems theory and practice: the need for a critical approach. Int. J. Gen. Syst. 10: 135- 151.

Jackson M.C. (1987a). New directions in management science. In Jackson M.C. and Keys P (eds.). New Directions in Management Science. Gower: Aldershot, UK, pp. 133-164.

Jackson M.C. (1987b). Present positions and future prospects in Management Science. Omega 15: 455-466.

Jackson M.C. (1990). Beyond a system of systems methodologies. J. Opl. Res. Soc. 41: 657-668.

Jackson M.C. (1991). Systems Methodology for the Management Sciences. Plenum: New York.

Jackson M.C. (1997). Pluralism in systems thinking and practice. In Mingers J. and Gill A. (eds.) (1997). Multimethodology: The Theory and Practice of Integrating Management Science Methodologies. Wiley: Chichester, UK, pp. 347-378.

Jackson M.C. (1999). Towards coherent pluralism in management science. J. Opl. Res. Soc. 50: 12-22.

Jackson M.C. (2000). Systems Approaches to Management. Kluwer/Plenum: New York.

Jackson M.C. (2003). Systems Thinking: Creative Holism for Managers. Wiley: Chichester, UK.

Jackson M.C. (2006a). Beyond problem structuring methods: reinventing the future of OR/MS. J. Opl. Res. Soc. 57: 868-878.

Jackson M.C. (2006b). Creative holism: a critical systems approach to complex problem situations. Syst. Res. 23: 647-657.

Jackson M.C. (2010). Reflections on the development and contribution of critical systems thinking and practice. Syst. Res. 27: 123-139.

Jackson M.C. and Keys P. (1984). Towards a system of system methodologies. J. Opl. Res. Soc. 35: 473-486.

Jackson M.C. and Keys P. (eds.) (1987). New Directions in Management Science. Gower: Aldershot, UK.

Kant I. (1781/1965). Critique of Pure Reason. Transl by N.K. Smith. St. Martin's Press: New York, 1965 (orig. Macmillan: London, 1929).

Keys P. (1987). Traditional management science and the emerging critique. In Jackson M.C. and Keys P. (eds.). New Directions in Management Science. Gower: Aldershot, UK, pp. 1-25.

Keys P. (1989). OR as technology: some issues and implications. J. Opl. Res. Soc. 40: 753-759.

Keys P. (ed.) (1995). Understanding the Process of Operational Research: Collected Readings. Wiley: Chichester.

Lewin K. (1946). Action research and minority problems. J. Soc. Issues 2(4): 34-46.

Midgley G. (1997). Mixing methods: developing systemic intervention. In Mingers J. and Gill A. (eds.). Multimethodology : The Theory and Practice of Integrating Management Science Methodologies. Wiley: Chichester, UK, pp. 249-290.

Mingers J. (1980). Towards an appropriate social theory for applied systems thinking: critical theory and soft systems methodology. J. Appl. Syst. Anal. 7: 41-49.

Mingers J. and Gill A. (eds.) (1997). Multimethodology : The Theory and Practice of Integrating Management Science Methodologies. Wiley: Chichester, UK.

Miser H.J. (1991). Comments on "OR as technology." J. Opl. Res. Soc. 42: 429-431.

Morgan G. (1986). Images of Organization. Sage: Beverly Hills, CA.

Muller-Merbach H. (1988). Mutual understanding revisited after nearly 25 years. Syst. Pract. 1: 385–397.

Ormerod R. (1996a). On the nature of OR – Entering the fray. J. Opl. Res. Soc. 47: 1-17.

Ormerod R. (1996b). Response to Miser: the objects and objectives of operational research (Viewpoint). J. Opl. Res. Soc. 47: 1325-1326.

Ormerod R. (2006). The history and ideas of pragmatism. J. Opl. Res. Soc. 57: 892-909.

Ormerod R. (2010a). Articulate intervention revisited. J. Opl. Res. Soc. 61: 1078-1094.

Ormerod R. (2010b). Justifying the methods of O.R. J. Opl. Res. Soc. 61: 1694-1708.

Ormerod R. (2016). On operationalizing critical pragmatism for professional practice: an open letter to Werner Ulrich. In Ulrich's Bimonthly, May-June 2016 (Reflections on Critical Pragmatism, Part 8).
[HTML]
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_may2016.html
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_may2016.pdf

Peirce C.S. (1878). How to make our ideas clear. Popular Science Monthly 12: 286-312. Reprinted in Hartshorne C. and Weiss P. (eds.). Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vol. V: Pragmatism and Pragmaticism. Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, 1934, pp. 248-271.

Pidd M. and Woolley R.N. (1980). A pilot study of problem structuring. J. Opl. Res. Soc. 31: 1063-1068.

Polya G. (1945). How to Solve It: A New Aspect of Mathematical Method. Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ.

Quade E.S. and Boucher W.I. (eds.) (1968). Systems Analysis and Policy Planning: Applications in Defense. American Elsevier: New York.

Reynolds M. (2007). Evaluation based on critical systems heuristics. In Williams B. and Imam I. (eds.). Systems Concepts in Evaluation: An Expert Anthology. Edge Press: Point Reyes, CA, pp. 101-122.

Rosenhead J. (1986). Custom and practice. J. Opl. Res. Soc. 32: 335-343.

Rosenhead J. (ed.) (1989). Rational Analysis for a Problematic World: Problem Structuring Methods for Complexity, Uncertainty and Conflict. Wiley: Chichester (rev. edn.,, Rational Analysis for a Problematic World Revisited, Rosenhead J. and Mingers J., eds., Wiley: Chichester, 2001).

Rosenhead J. and Thunhurst C. (1982). A materialist analysis of operational research. J. Opl. Res. Soc. 33: 111–122.

Schein E.A. (1969). Process Consultation: Its Role in Organization Development. Addison-Wesley: Reading, MA.

Ulrich W. (1977). The design of problem-solving systems. Mngt. Sci. 23: 1099-1108.

Ulrich W. (1980a). The metaphysics of design: a Simon-Churchman debate. Interfaces 10(2): 35-40.

Ulrich W. (1980b). Epistemological Foundations of a Critical Systems Approach for Social Planners: From Critical Rationalism and Critical Theory to Critical Heuristics. Ph.D. Dissertation, University of California, Berkeley: Interdisciplinary Ph.D. Program of the Graduate Division, Nov. 13, 1980. Available from University Microfilm International: Ann Arbor, MI, 1981.

Ulrich W. (1981a). On blaming the messenger for the bad news: reply to Bryer's "Comments." Omega 9: 7.

Ulrich W. (1981b). A critique of pure cybernetic reason: the Chilean experience with cybernetics. J. Appl. Syst. Anal. 8: 1981, pp. 33-59.

Ulrich W. (1981c). Systemrationalität und praktische Vernunft – Gedanken zum Stand des Systemansatzes. In Churchman C.W. Der Systemansatz und seine Feinde. [Translator's introduction to an annotated German translation of "The Systems Approach and its Enemies"]. Haupt: Bern, pp. 7-37.

Ulrich W. (1983). Critical Heuristics of Social Planning: A New Approach to Practical Philosophy. Haupt: Bern (pb. reprint edn., Wiley: Chichester, UK, 1994).

Ulrich W. (1987). Critical heuristics of social systems design. Europ. J. Opl. Res. 31: 276-283.

Ulrich W. (1988). Systems thinking, systems practice, and practical philosophy: a program of research. Syst. Pract. 1: 137–163. [/1247]

Ulrich W. (1993). Some difficulties of ecological thinking, considered from a critical systems perspective: a plea for critical holism. Syst. Pract. 6: 583-611.

Ulrich W. (1996). A Primer to Critical Systems Heuristics for Action Researchers. Centre for Systems Studies, University of Hull: Hull, UK (31 March 1996). Digital version of 10 August 2014, available in Werner Ulrich's Home Page, Downloads Section.
[PDF] http://wulrich.com/downloads/ulrich_1996a.pdf

Ulrich W. (2000). Reflective practice in the civil society: the contribution of critically systemic thinking. Reflect. Pract. 1: 247-268.

Ulrich W. (2001). The quest for competence in systemic research and practice. Syst. Res. 18: 3-28.

Ulrich W. (2003). Beyond methodology choice: critical systems thinking as critically systemic discourse. J. Opl. Res. Soc. 54: 325-342.

Ulrich W. (2004). Obituary: C West Churchman, 1913-2004. J. Opl. Res. Soc. 55: 1123-1129.

Ulrich W. (2005). A brief introduction to critical systems heuristics (CSH). ECOSENSUS project site, The Open University, Milton Keynes, UK.
[HTML] http://kmi.open.ac.uk/projects/ecosensus/publications/ (also available from the author's home page at http://wulrich.com/downloads/).

Ulrich W. (2006). Critical pragmatism: a new approach to professional and business ethics. In Zsolnai L. (ed.). Interdisciplinary Yearbook of Business Ethics, Vol. 1. Peter Lang: Oxford, UK, pp. 53-85.

Ulrich W. (2007). Philosophy for professionals: towards critical pragmatism. J. Opl. Res. Soc. 58: 1109-1113.

UlricW. (2012a). Operational research and critical systems thinking – an integrated perspective. Part 1: OR as applied systems thinking. J. Opl. Res. Soc. 63: 1228-1247.

UlricW. (2012b). Operational research and critical systems thinking – an integrated perspective. Part 2: OR as argumentative practice. J. Opl. Res. Soc. 63: 1307-1322.

Ulrich W. (2013). Critical systems thinking. In Gass S.I. and Fu M.C. (eds.). Encyclopedia of Operations Research and Management Science, 3rd edn. (2 vols.). Springer: New York, pp. 314-326. Prepublication version: CST's two ways: a concise account of critical systems thinking. Ulrich's Bimonthly, November-December 2012.
[HTML]
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_november2012.html
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_november2012.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2016). Philosophy for professionals: towards critical pragmatism. Reflections on Critical Pragmatism, Part 7. Ulrich's Bimonthly, March-April 2016 (earlier version in: Journal of the Operational Research Society, 58, No. 8, 2007, pp. 1109-1113).
[HTML] http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_march2016.html
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_march2016.pdf

Ulrich W. and Reynolds M. (2010). Critical systems heuristics. In Reynolds M. and Holwell S. (eds.). Systems Approaches to Managing Change: A Practical Guide. Springer: London, pp. 243-292.

Vickers G. (1965). The Art of Judgement: A Study of Policy Making. Chapman & Hall: London.

Weber M. (1949). "Objectivity" in social science and social policy. In Shils E.A. and Finch H.A. (eds.). The Methodology of the Social Sciences. Free Press: New York, pp. 72-111.

Woolley R.N. and Pidd M. (1981). Problem structuring – a literature review. J. Opl. Res. Soc. 32: 197-206.

 

Picture data  Digital photograph taken on 16 July 2013 around 6:00 p.m. at Lake Thun, Switzerland. ISO 200, exposure mode aperture priority, with aperture f/9.9, exposure time 1/200 seconds, and exposure bias -0.667. Metering mode multi-segment, contrast low, saturation high, sharpness low. Focal length 20 mm, equivalent to 32 mm with a conventional 35 mm camera (i.e., with a full-format sensor). 5184 x 3456 pixels; current resolution 700 x 525 pixels, compressed to 108 KB.

July-August, 2016

 

Steamboat on stormy Lake Thun - balancing technical and contextual competence

 It's all about combining technical with contextual competence: steamboat journey on stormy Lake Thun 

 

Ensuring a healthy balance between technical and contextual sophistication is vital to all professional practice.”

(From this essay about the value of integrating operations research and critical systems thinking)

Notepad for capturing personal thoughts  »

Previous Picture

Next Picture  

Personal notes:

Write down your thoughts before you forget them!
Just be sure to copy them elsewhere before leaving this page.

 

 

 

 

 

 

Last updated 31 Jul 2016; first published 24 Jul 2016
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_july2016.html

Home

Top / Menu

Site Map

Copyright