|
|
The argument for a communicative turn of rational
ethics (continued)
This
edition of the Bimonthly continues the preparatory exploration
of discourse ethics on which we embarked in the last edition
(see Ulrich, 2010a). The idea is to explore two more approximations
to this difficult topic. First, I will continue the argument
for a cognitivst conception of ethics, communicatively turned,
with somewhat different means, by inviting Habermas to join
us in a fictitious dialogue. This format allows for a more informal
style than ordinary academic writing, and thus (I hope) may
make Habermas' thinking a bit more accessible.
Second,
our exploration will turn to the issue of how we can conceive
of moral reasoning in today's world of ethical pluralism and
relativism. This issue should allow us to familiarize ourselves
with one particular aspect of discourse ethics that is most
important for understanding and appreciating its aims, as well
as for seeing its practical limitations, I mean its underlying
moral universalism – the idea that moral claims hold
universally or are no moral claims at all. It's a difficult
position to maintain nowadays, one that I do not share unreservedly
but which Habermas believes
is indispensable. In this respect, as in many other respects,
discourse ethics follows the path of rational ethics first explored
by Immanuel Kant (1786, 1787; cf. our previous detailed discussion
in Ulrich, 2009b). It will therefore be useful to return once
more to some of Kant's seminal ideas and to see discourse ethics
in their light. However, we will start this second half of our
exploration with a short glimpse back at Aristotle.
The
argument for a communicative turn of rational ethics (Version 2)
A
frequent objection to the idea of rational ethics has
to do with doubts about the reach of reason. Reason is able
to justify the efficacy of means with a view to given ends,
the argument says, but it cannot justify the ends themselves. This sort
of doubt has been articulated from many different philosophical
positions, ranging from logical positivism and critical
rationalism to post-modernism. It stands in opposition to
a richer conception of practical reason that originated
in the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle (1976, 1985,
cf. Ulrich,
2009a) and culminated
in Kant's rational ethics (cf. Ulrich, 2009b). To be sure,
for Aristotle it was still the polis rather than
critical reason which ultimately determined what was virtuous
and right; but he was the first philosopher to give practical
reason its own, genuine rationality, which distinguished
it from theoretical reason and pointed the way to Kant's
later notion of "pure" practical reason.
Recovering
the practical dimension of reason
In After Virtue, Alasdair
MacIntyre (1981) offers an interesting account of the historical
changes
that led to the loss of this richer conception of practical
reason and thus led to
our contemporary doubts about the possibility of cognitive ethics.
To Aristotle, practical reason was
the faculty that allowed men to understand the human telos
(i.e., finality) and potential of unfolding their true, virtuous nature or, as
MacIntyre puts it, man-as-he-could-be-if-he-realized-his-essential-nature
as distinguished
from man-as-he-happens-to-be (1981, p. 52). "Ethics
is the science which is to enable men to understand how they make the transition."
(1981, p. 52) Aristotle's concept of practical reason
is thus teleological but not merely instrumental, for it
also instructs us about the telos itself. Due to its
roots in the traditions of the polis, Aristotelian
reason could still inform us about both what our true ends were
(an issue of practical reason) and how to reach them (an issue
of theoretical reason). But with the advent of religious conceptions of morality in medieval
times and with the subsequent de facto failure of the Enlightenment
project, things changed. Reason lost its power of determining both
virtuous
ends and virtues courses of action leading toward them:
Anti-Aristotelian
science sets strict boundaries to the powers of reason. Reason
[now] is calculative; it can assess truths of fact and mathematical
relations but nothing more. In the realm of practice therefore
it can speak only of means. About ends it must be silent. (MacIntyre,
1981, p. 54)
Against
this disempowerment of reason, and citing MacIntyres's account
of it, Habermas (1990a, pp. 43-57) advocates the need
for maintaining, with Aristotle and Kant, the conception of
rational or "cognitive" ethics and, implicitly, the
notion of a genuinely practical form of reason that supports
it. With MacIntyre, Habermas is not prepared to accept the idea
that reason is merely calculative. That would leave us with
"an instrumental reason restricted to purposive rationality
[that] must let its ends be determined by blind emotional attitudes
and arbitrary decisions" (1990a, p. 43, with unspecific references
to MacIntyre and M. Horkheimer). It would, if I interpret
Habermas (1990a, pp. 52-55) correctly, amount either to some form of ethical intuitionism,
which constructs ethical propositions according to the model
of intuitive knowledge (i.e., theoretical reason) and thereby loses sight of the concept
of practical reason from the outset, or else to ethical emotivism
or decisionism, which both narrow practical reason down to instrumental
reason:
- Ethical
intuitionism understands moral judgments, along
with all other kinds of normative statements, as an
expression of intuitive ethical knowledge in which we
recognize an action or situation to be "good"
in much the same way as we recognize a table to be "yellow";
that is, we grasp ethical qualities analogously to the
way we perceive the properties of things (Moore, 1903),
prior to and without the need for any kind of rational
deliberation or argumentation.
- Ethical emotivism assumes
that all normative statements, including moral judgments,
express an emotional
stance rather than a rational validity claim and thus
cannot
be argued to be right or wrong; we can describe them empirically
(e.g., psychologically) but not justify them philosophically.
- Ethical decisionism sees
in moral judgments acts of volition that belong to a
nonrational
domain of merely subjective value judgments grounded in
cultural,
ideological, and psychological conditions rather than in generally
(e.g., cross-culturally) defendable reasons; and ultimately,
- Ethical skepticism
quite generally assumes an agnostic position – we
never know that any moral claim is true
or right in any definitive sense.
All
these noncognitivist conceptions of ethics are unable "to
explain what it might mean for normative propositions to be
true" (Habermas, 1990a, p. 56). They can therefore
not be regarded as an adequate basis for moral theory. There
would be no rational grounds to maintain the
idea that
reason unfolds not only through theoretical (empirical,
instrumental)
but equally through practical (normative, moral)
reasoning.
We would consequently have no way to promote ethical
practice except by appealing to the good will and
virtuousness
of people. We might be able to
explain why a certain way of acting is right for us
individually,
but not why someone else (much less, everybody) ought
to consider it right. It would then be difficult to
advance any rational
grounds for moral claims, as the only rational way in which
we can hope
to resolve ethical clashes. We must therefore maintain that
"moral judgments have cognitive content," in the
sense that "they
represent more than expressions
of the contingent emotions, preferences, and decisions
of a
speaker or actor." (Habermas, 1990a,
p. 120). This is what cognitive ethics is all about.
Cognitive
ethics: communicative rather than communitarian…
Up to this point, Habermas agrees with MacIntyre's quest
for recovering the practical dimension of reason. But Habermas
does not want to follow MacIntyre's plea for a return to the
Aristotelian tradition of an ethics of virtue or to some neo-Aristotelian
"communitarian" version of it. He clearly prefers
(although
he does not say it so directly) to salvage the
option of cognitive ethics by giving it a communicative rather than communitarian twist.
A communicative turn replaces the normatively charged telos
of conducting a good and virtuous
life according to the traditioned values of the polis – the communitarian core of Aristotelian
ethics – with the procedural rather than substantive aim of mutual understanding.
As the reader will remember, formal pragmatics has shown this
aim to be an unavoidable element of
the general pragmatic presuppositions of argumentation, presuppositions
that we have also described as general symmetry conditions of
rational
speech (Ulrich, 2009d, p. 23). To be sure, these presuppositions
are not free of all a normative content; for example, we may
understand them to embody the utopia of a peaceful and rationally
motivated settlement of conflicts. However, this normative content
is minimal in the sense that the
presuppositions
in question are built
into the deep structure of language, which means that they are
involved in all attempts,
across all cultures and epochs, to coordinate people's actions
communicatively. Whatever the specific values of a community
may be, a communicative rather than communitarian approach to
ethics maintains that the only enlightened way to settle normative
conflicts is by allowing people to argue their concerns freely
rather than subjecting them to the non-argumentative rule of
tradition and power.
… with
a renewed teleological core While
we are sufficiently familiar with that part of Habermas' argument
and need not repeat it, a different aspect emerges here:
situating discourse ethics against the background of Aristotelian
and communitarian ethics sheds a new light
on Apel and Habermas' proposition of a linguistic
telos of mutual
understanding. Suddenly,
the "formal-pragmatic" postulate of an in-built finality of language
looks like a distant remnant of the stronger teleological element
in Aristotle's practical philosophy, an element that Kant had
meant to eliminate from his concept of (pure) practical reason. Neither
Apel nor Habermas has to my knowledge explained the postulate
of a linguistic telos in this
way. Particularly when it comes to its importance for a communicative
turn of cognitive ethics, this circumstance is hardly surprising,
as their notion of morality is deontological rather than
teleological (i.e., morality is about what we – all of us –
ought to do in principle rather than what we may wish
to achieve in a particular context of action). Even so, I find it interesting to observe that their
linguistic framework effectively reintroduces
into Kantian ethics a hint of Aristotelian teleological reasoning.
Between the lines, we read this
message: the
telos of mutual understanding embodies the minimum
teleological orientation that enables practical reason
to recover its own, genuine rationality, so that even under
contemporary conditions of cultural diversity it may still do
the trick and instruct us about proper ends of practice
– of intersubjectively
good practice, that is. In this minimal sense, then, the "modern"
suspicion mentioned at the outset turns out to be correct: rationality means
reasoning for, or towards, some finality. But of course,
practical reasoning hardly differs from theoretical
reasoning in this respect. What separates the two forms of rationality
is only the different nature of
their finalities – knowledge and instrumental know-how in the case of theoretical reason,
mutual understanding and cooperative action in the case of practical reason.
A
fictitious discussion with Habermas We
have
thus far followed Habermas only roughly. Formulating
things in our own words, and following up conjectures that offer
themselves, may help us in understanding a difficult author. Just repeating things more
or less literally does not secure
learning. At the same time, however,
it is also important to make sure we give an authentic account
of Habermas' ideas, lest we comment on ideas nobody actually
holds. Particularly when it comes to criticism, critical comments
that are not grounded in an accurate and fair account are meaningless.
So, we always need to keep a balance between these two means
of learning. Perhaps we should invite Habermas to join our discussion
for a while? As I know from my own encounter with him, he is
such a friendly, amiable person! Let us imagine he joins in
at this point:
„Hello
everyone, thanks for inviting me to join your discussion. What
I've heard you saying about MacIntyre's plea for a revival
of Aristotelian practical reason is quite interesting. But of course, I
am not exactly a communitarian and I hope I have made that sufficiently clear in my writings. If you
agree, I would prefer to pursue the argument for a renewed cognitivism
in ethics in one or two other directions, say, with considerations
inspired
by analytical philosophy, linguistics, and argumentation theory rather than
by neo-Aristotelian thinking. Or, to offer you an alternative,
I also find it important to
connect moral theory with the phenomenology of the moral,
that is, with the way we actually experience moral phenomena
in the social lifeworld. It gives us a chance to discover
the cognitive foundation of moral experience. Likewise,
I find it useful to draw on developmental
psychology in the tradition of Piaget and Kohlberg, we can learn so
much from it about the kind of
cognitive skills and competencies involved in moral judgment, and
about how these skills grow in our childhood through processes of
learning and socialization.”
„All
options sound interesting,”
you (the reader) may want to suggest; „but since you give
us a choice, why not pursue a new track of argumentation
that we haven't encountered thus far? We have already familiarized
ourselves a bit with the ideas of Piaget and Kohlberg earlier
on, and also have examined the argumentation theory of Toulmin
though not in its application to ethics, so perhaps you
could first tell us something about the way you apply it
to ethics and then, if time remains, we might take up the
"moral experience" track you mentioned?”
„Yes,
fine. To begin with Stephen Toulmin's work on argumentation
theory, it is important to me also in the realm of ethics.
Since you are already familiar with it, I can be rather brief on this and we
can then dedicate a bit more
time, I would suggest, to Peter Strawson's
(1974) work on the phenomenology of the moral. You know,
Strawson is a fine analytical philosopher, especially as
a theorist of ordinary language, but he's also a Kantian
scholar interested in moral theory and even in transcendental
philosophy. I have therefore found it very meaningful to draw
on his work, as a source that adds some interesting elements
to my argument for a cognitivist foundation of discourse
ethics.”
Drawing
on Toulmin „Let
me situate the first argument a bit, I mean the argument drawing on Toulmin,” Habermas suggests,
„by relating it to Kant's rather than Aristotle's notion
of practical reason. Kant is the philosopher of Enlightenment.
An enlightened notion of practical reason relies on the idea
that the court of reason, rather than the church
or the polis or any other authority, is to provide
the 'highest tribunal' of what is true and right. So it
is clear that from a Kantian perspective, we must see in
the disempowerment of practical reason subsequent to Aristotle
– After Virtue, I am tempted to say with MacIntyre (1981) –
a consequence of what medieval scholasticism
and modernity have made of it, rather than an inherent limitation
of our rational faculties to merely 'calculative' questions
of purposiveness. In the scholastic age, MacIntyre would probably
say, reason had to be powerless
in matters of ethics because all power regarding the proper
way to live was laying with God. In the age of science, I would
add, practical reason has to be powerless because the
limits of the rational have become identified with those of
the scientific. But the idea of practical reason, and with it
the notion of rational ethics,
is bound to become meaningless if in the first place we refer
all ethical questions to an external (divine or other) authority that does the reasoning
for us, so that all that remains to us is an act of faith; likewise,
it becomes meaningless if we first situate it within the bounds
of theoretical reason, so that science and theoretical or instrumental
reason are by definition the proper tools to guide us.”
„To
put it differently: from an argumentation-theoretical
point of view it is pointless to reduce
practical to instrumental reason, for these two kinds of rationality
address different questions; questions that complement rather than replace
one another. Rational ethics addresses questions
that do not in the first place concern either purpose-rational
action (i.e., matters of theoretical-instrumental rationality)
or acts of faith related to one's individual form of life (i.e.,
matters of personal ethos); rather, it addresses questions that
concern the interpersonal consequences of our ethical choices
and actions (i.e., matters of moral defensibility or tenability). Such
questions are of a 'cognitive' nature not only in
the trivial sense that they require from us some knowledge or anticipation
of empirical consequences (an issue of theoretical reason) but also in
the more specific sense that they compel us to judge these consequences.
They require us to examine the extent to which we can make
an argument for the normative claims and consequences involved (an issue of practical reason). 'To
say that I ought to do something means that I have
good reasons for doing it' (Habermas, 1990a, p. 49)
–
reasons in the Kantian, moral sense of practical reason. To deny the existence of practical reason
would mean we deny the possibility of any standards by which
we might reasonably assess the moral acceptability of our actions;
it would imply a stance of total moral nihilism.”
Declaring
the death of practical reason is besides the point
„But
proposing the
death of practical reason, after first depriving it of any standards
of morality and thereby reducing it to merely instrumental
reason, is (to use Toulmin's phrase) besides the point. The
question is not whether practical reason exists but only, what
we make of it, that is, what intersubjectively acceptable standards
of rationality (or reasonableness) we want to associate with
it. The conception of the moral point of view (Baier,
1958) provides
an essential clue: it defines a perspective from which
we can indeed judge moral claims reasonably, namely, by assessing
their consequences against a genuinely intersubjective
standard such as reciprocity or, more specifically, impartiality.”
„Let
me continue this thread a little further,” Habermas continues
after pausing for a moment. „What I've just tried to explain
is a crucial point for me. For as soon as we understand practical questions from
a thus-understood moral point of view – a moral perspective
tied to the standard of impartiality – they gain what
I call a cognitive meaning, in that they now relate
to a validity basis that we can defend or challenge argumentatively.
To that precise extent,” Habermas adds emphatically, „we may
say that 'practical questions admit
of truth', that is, the answers we give can be shown to be right
or wrong.” (1975, p. 111; 1990a, pp. 43 and 51f)
„Yes,
but … hmm … may I try and reformulate what you just said
a
little bit, if you don't mind, to help us understand?” I
ask, slightly puzzled. – „Feel free.” – „Isn't
it so that strictly speaking, 'practical questions' do not
really demand evidence for truth, they demand reasons
for rightness, right? So what you say is that inasmuch as
we consider practical questions
from the moral point of view, we can discuss about them with genuinely
practical reasons – reasons that we can argue but which
are not of a theoretical or instrumental nature. The crucial
point, then, it seems to me, is not truth but argumentation:
we can and need to advance reasons for rightness just
like for truth. So, could I redefine your statement
by
saying that 'practical questions admit of reasons'?”
– „You could!” Habermas
replies with a nod of assent, and offers the following explanation.
Ethics
as argumentation theory „You
have complained that in my writings on discourse ethics,
I discuss so many different sources. One reason why I find
this useful is that all those contemporary moral theorists
in the tradition of Aristotle and Kant on whom I draw, among
them Kurt Baier (1958), Marcus Singer (1961), John Rawls
(1971) and, most important to me, Karl Otto Apel (1972,
1975), share one central intent. As I wrote in my 'Notes'
on a program of philosophical justification for discourse
ethics, they 'all share the intention
of analyzing the conditions for making impartial judgments of
practical questions, judgments based solely on reasons.'
(1990a, p. 43) There
you go.… It makes sense to me indeed to understand discourse
ethics as a special theory of argumentation, as I
suggested in the 'Notes' (1990a, p. 44); a theory of
impartial argumentation about the specific kind of
normative issues that we designate moral questions. How
can such arguments be cogent, what role can reasons
can play in them? To clarify this issue I draw on Toulmin's
(2003, orig. 1958) seminal work on argumentation theory:
More precisely, I draw on the way I have adopted Toulmin's
work in my formal pragmatics. Obviously the communicative turn of
ethics, too, comes into play through this argumentation-theoretical
approach. It all boils down to this: discourse ethics
is an attempt to explain, via a communicative
reading of the moral point of view, how moral theory
can be recasted in the form of an analysis of moral argumentation.”
(cf. Habermas, 1990a, p. 57)
„You
mean, discourse ethics is simply a specific kind of argumentation
theory? Specific in that it aims to explain the old concept
of practical reason in new, argumentative terms?” – „That's
right. Practical reason is the
idea that we can respond to moral questions, no less than
to theoretical questions, with reason. That is, not
just emotionally or with subjective preferences, but by
advancing reasons that others may share, reasons of a specific
kind. They must have a cognitive content that can be argued
to be right or wrong, that's why they cannot just be emotions
or personal value preferences, subjective acts of faith
or 'decisions', and so on. We must be able to substantiate
them, that is, to explain why they deserve recognition
by others across all differences of needs and interests,
worldviews and values. Discourse ethics examines what kind
of reasons these can be and how we can hope to justify them.
You see, once we have clarified this issue, we can then
apply Toulmin's general model of substantive argumentation,
or the way I have adopted it in formal pragmatics. Thus
discourse
ethics provides the missing link between the
'old' concept of practical reason and the 'modern' concept
of a pragmatic logic of substantive argumentation.”
Drawing
on Strawson „But let us now turn to
the
second argument. It takes up an analysis offered by P. Strawson
(1974) of the nature of moral phenomena as we encounter them
through personal moral experience, and it finds this experience
rooted
in a cognitive foundation (cf. Habermas, 1990a, pp. 45-50,
and 1993b, p. 39f). To understand this cognitive foundation,
we need first of all to understand why moral
experiences are so important to us. It is because they originate
in 'that complicated web of attitudes and feelings which
form moral life as we know it' (Strawson, 1974, p. 24) and on which
depend not only our experiences with others but also our feelings
and attitudes
towards ourselves (1974, p. 6). I am thinking, for example,
of feelings and attitudes such as individual confidence
and mutual trust; of the ability to take a
cooperative attitude and also experience it on the part
of others; of feeling free to express oneself authentically,
of
seeing oneself as a participant rather than observer; and so on.”
„When
this web of mutual normative expectations and attitudes
gets disrupted, we feel cheated, powerless, speechless:
our cooperative attitude is questioned, communicative practice
is at peril. We suddenly become observers rather than participants,
albeit emotionally injured rather than calm and objective
observers. Conversely, when we ourselves violate this web
of expectations, we experience feelings of guilt or bad
conscience, observing our own behavior as it were. These
emotional responses are the moral phenomena we are talking
about. They point to unresolved
moral issues – issues of reciprocity and fairness – which may endanger or
disrupt this finely woven web of social expectations. That explains why
they often raise in us strong feelings of indignation; a sense
of unfairness, of personal insult and injury. If the situation
is not cleared up, it may result in lasting resentment.”
„Accordingly important it becomes that we
can repair the damage – avoid lasting resentment, regain a sense
of mutual goodwill – by articulating our feelings. That
may make us feel better, but more importantly, it allows
and at times challenges those concerned to explain and excuse their
ways of behaving, so that we may understand and resolve
the issue. For example, it helps if we understand that those
who violated our expectations 'had no choice'
to act differently or 'did not know' about certain aspects of
the situation; or conversely, if we can explain and excuse
ourselves by pointing out, where necessary, that we were
'not aware' of how others see an issue or 'did not mean it that way',
and so on.
That may bring into play a sense of objectivity and paradoxically,
precisely through this sense of objectivity, may help us recover
a sense of unimpaired intersubjectivity, so that we can
be participants once again.” (cf. Strawson, 1974, pp. 7-10;
Habermas, 1990a, pp. 45-48)
From
moral phenomena to practical discourse „You
may wonder why I am saying all these things about our emotional responses
to goodwill or its absence, as Strawson (1974, p. 7)
describes them. Much of it is commonplace,
and I am not a psychologist after all. Nor is Peter Strawson
a psychologist. His interest is
of a linguistic nature, as is mine. One important point
is that the unresolved moral issues of which these responses
are an expression have to do with the loss of that essential
sense of unimpaired subjectivity about which I have just
been talking; or linguistically speaking, with the loss
of a shared validity basis of speech. Unless it can
be reestablished, communicative practice risks breaking
down. Formal pragmatics has taught us that in such moments,
what matters is that those involved are prepared to redeem
their claims with reasons that everyone can accept of their
own free will:
The
fact that a speaker can rationally motivate a hearer [...] is
due not to the validity of what he says but to the speaker's
guarantee that he will, if necessary, make efforts to redeem
the claim that the hearer has accepted. It is this guarantee
that effects the coordination between speaker and hearer. (Habermas,
1990a, p. 58f)
Communicative
practice depends on such a validity basis. This is no news.
The only thing that is new is that the meaning of 'redeeming'
has changed. We now need a specifically practical
kind of reasons with which we can justify normative claims.
There must be such reasons, for as I put it earlier:
To
say that I ought to do something means that I have
good reasons for doing it. (1990a, p. 49)
But
what kind of good reasons allow us to justify normative
claims? Strawson's analysis points to the kind of reasons
we need. They should help us in reestablishing the sense
of unimpaired intersubjectivity that has been lost or is
at peril. Why is it at peril? Because someone has disrupted
the finespun web of mutually cooperative attitudes and expectations.
Someone has put egocentric motives first, has in some way
instrumentalized the good will of others for his own purposes.
Our emotional response to such situations is of a moral
nature, and the same holds consequently true for the cognitive
basis of argumentation we are searching. This is where I
locate the crucial link between moral phenomena
and communicative rationality. The way Kant already
tied the moral to the rational thus appears in a new, communicative
light.”
The
validity basis of practical discourse „Ah!
Thank you, Professor Habermas, I think we are beginning
to understand. The cognitive foundation of morality is the
conditio sine qua non for your communicative turn
of ethics, because only so can we hope to identify a specifically
moral, yet general validity basis of
practical discourse, right? So, if we want to understand
that validity basis,
the next and crucial question must be: What kind of 'good
reasons'
can justify a moral claim?”
„Exactly. As I've said earlier,
discourse ethics finds the validity basis of normative
justifications in a reinterpretation of the moral point of
view in discursive terms. Remember the basic idea is
that from a moral point of view, we try to judge things
impartially, so as to do equal justice to all. 'Equal
justice' means not that we treat everyone the same but rather,
that we treat everyone with equal consideration and respect,
with fairness. You might ask, why should we rely
on just this one criterion
of impartiality, isn't that arbitrary? The point is, impartiality
in this sense of fairness is the only standard of which
we can safely say that it supplies a genuinely practical
and at the same time a truly general reason. It has
normative force, yet embodies
a standard to which everyone can appeal at all times, for
it is truly 'suprapersonal' (Habermas, 1990a, p. 48)
– the very contrary of any attempt to impose merely egocentric,
particular, nongeneralizable interests, or
to instrumentalize people in any way. It is what Kant's categorical
imperative was all about.”
„The
other basic idea that comes into play with the communicative turn
of ethics is that impartiality is now a matter of discourse rather than
just individual reflection. We switch from an observer's to a participant's
perspective, but the aim remains the same. We
still want to assure ourselves that the norm or principle
informing our action – or with Kant, the maxim guiding us
– is one we can defend publicly, if we are challenged to justify
it. The only way we can make sure this is so is if we have reason on our side, in the form of the one
and only 'good reason' that nobody can doubt: we
do equal justice to everyone concerned. The norm on which
we rely could be everyone's norm:
its consequences are fair to all. And how do we make
sure this is so? By submitting our personal reasons (or
motives, if you want) to the scrutiny of the other parties
concerned. Reasons that survive the discourse (provided
it is a discourse regulated by the general pragmatic presuppositions
of formal pragmatics) are those which come close to embodying
a generalizable norm in the sense of impartiality or fairness.
In this way, the moral point of view enriches and completes
the 'universal validity basis of speech' with a genuinely
practical (read moral) moment. We have gained a general
validity basis that allows us to explain how, in principle,
normative judgments can be justified discursively.”
So
what? „The
result is what I would call a 'presuppositional justification' (1990a,
p. 82) of the moral point of view, cognitively interpreted
and communicatively turned. In plain language: the
only perspective from which we can hope to decide rationally
about normative claims is a thus reconstructed moral point of
view. It is the conditio sine qua non, as
you suggested – or
in Kantian terms, the condition of the possibility – of practical
discourse. Discourse ethics explains why this is so, and what
it means in terms of argumentative conditions and principles.
Indirectly, discourse ethics thus becomes a moral theory
that explains the nature of morality in the terms of a special
theory
of argumentation. But excuse me, I have been talking for
quite a while … I have someone waiting for me, may I let
you continue on your own?”
„Yes
of course, thank you very much, Professor Habermas. It has
been very interesting to listen to you! I think we have
learned a lot that will help us in better understanding
your ideas about discourse ethics. For example, I think
you have made us appreciate, through your account of Strawson's
work, why moral theory is so important for your project
of a communicative rationalization of society. It is, as
Strawson helps us to understand, because unresolved moral
issues undermine the basis for communicative practice, and
thus for communicative rationality. As a second major example,
I think what you've said about Toulmin's work throws an
interesting new light on the crucial link that Kant established
between the moral and the rational. Kant's notion of practical
reason is alive, we can still learn about new facets of
it and we still cannot do without it. But I don't want to
prolong, you must go. ”
– „Don't worry, I have a couple of minutes left, go ahead.”
A
brief summary and reply „I think you have
made us appreciate two basic points. First, to understand
what moral judgments and claims mean, we need to understand
how we can argue them – your argumentation-theoretical
turn of moral theory (and thus, of practical reason). And
second, to understand how we can argue about moral questions,
we need to understand how the general pragmatic presuppositions
of argumentation that you explain in the terms of formal
pragmatics translate into specific criteria for moral
argumentation, if any such criteria are available at all
– the missing link between the idea of practical reason
and Toulmin's model of substantive argumentation on the
one hand, and your quest for a communicative rationalization
of society on the other hand.”
„Yes,
so what did you hear me saying about such specific criteria?”
Habermas encourages me to conclude the point.
„Well,
in addition to the presuppositions of substantive
argumentation that you have derived from Toulmin's model
of argumentation, and also in addition to the basic linguistic
telos of mutual understanding that you have worked
out together with Apel, it seems to me you have drawn our
attention today to at least two specific requirements of
moral discourse. On the one hand, we have learned how important
it is that we conceive of morality from a participant's rather
than an observer's perspective. If you allow me to say
it with my own words, moral argumentation is not only about
arguments, as it were, but also about turning those concerned
into participants. Taking them seriously, that is. This
is a specifically moral dimension of communicative rationality
to which we may need to give more attention than it has
traditionally received in Kantian ethics, I suspect; perhaps
also more attention than you have given it in formal pragmatics
thus far? Taking people seriously, that is, regardless
of how good they are at arguing their case. I fear adequate
participation and cogent argumentation may at times be in
conflict (an issue that has interested me in my work on
critical heuristics). On the other hand, and perhaps in
partial response to this concern, I think we are beginning
to grasp the special role of the viewpoint of impartiality,
or what Baier has called the moral point of view. Not all
the people concerned can always become involved, and not
all involved are argumentatively skilled. Participation
is good, but impartiality is better, you make us understand,
for it makes sure the outcome of a moral discourse is sound
regardless of whether all those concerned are present and
get heard. When it comes to moral questions, complete and
equal participation of all those concerned may have to remain
an ideal, but examining the arguments of those involved
against the standard of impartiality is always possible,
right?”
„So,”
I conclude, „if you'd ask me to sum up what I think I have
learned today about discourse ethics, it seems to me that
in essence it tries to explain morality in the terms of
a theory of impartial argumentation. May I put it
this way? It's not a formula that I find in your writings,
but it seems to capture what you've told us today. Or does
it miss what you meant to tell us?” – „No, it doesn't. In
fact, this way of putting the idea of discourse ethics leads
directly to another important concern that I associate with
it, I mean my attempt to revive Kant's moral universalism.
You may want to have a look at this issue, it may provide
another chance for you to familiarize yourself with the
aims of discourse ethics. But now I really have to run.”
– „Thank you very much again!” – „You're welcome.
Bye now!”
[End
of fictitious dialogue]
The
argument for reviving moral universalism in a pluralistic
world
Two
basic options When we face the kind
of ethical clashes
that we designate moral questions, we have
no choice but indeed, to make a choice. We can either decide
in favor of what is good for some of those involved,
or we can search for a shared notion of what is equally
good for all those concerned. The first option implies
that some of those concerned will benefit and others will
not. Those in a position to control things will
usually make sure they benefit. The second option implies that we
apply some standard of fairness that does equal justice to all.
All the parties concerned will (ideally) get a chance to
argue their concerns and in the end, to agree or not depending
on whether they find the outcome fair. Inasmuch as actual involvement is not feasible,
those involved can at least apply that same standard to reflect
and
argue on behalf of those affected
but not involved. So much for the two basic options, to
which Habermas in other contexts (especially of action theory
and social theory) also refers as the two ideal types of
strategic vs. communicative action. Real-world practice,
to be sure, will often involve a mixture of the two pure types. In addition,
the "second best" option of responsible (i.e., not
merely strategic) though monological (i.e., reflective rather
than communicative) action also plays a relevant role in practice,
although it has no place in Habermas' typology (I'll subsume
it under communicative action).
The
implication of this basic choice is clear. Unless we wish to act merely
strategically, we have no choice but to take a moral stance
and to pursue it by both dialogical and reflective means. The general question with which
formal pragmatics deals, the question of what communicative
rationality means – of how we can identify and substantiate it – then
translates into the more specific question of what it means to act rationally
with a view to doing equal justice
to all, rather than just pursuing our own advantage: How can we identify and justify
the "communicatively" (rather than just strategically)
rational quality of the way we deal with normative issues? This
is what discourse ethics is to add to formal pragmatics:
it needs to explain the conditions under which communicative
practice could effectively be shown to be moral.
The
universalistic thrust of communicative rationality
The
"equal justice to all" or "equally good for all"
requirement mentioned above points to the difficulty in question.
It not only functions as a warrant of impartiality, it also
stands for the universalistic
thrust of all rational ethics, and thus of all moral claims
that we wish to associate with communicative action. Communicative
rationality cannot arbitrarily exclude from participation anyone who may have something
to say on a validity claim at issue. Discourse about moral claims
makes no exception.
Equal justice
is either equal justice to all, or it is no equal justice
at all. Moral justification therefore implies a claim for warranted
universal assertibilty or, as we said earlier with Silber's
(1974, p. 217) apt phrase, for "universal
communicability" of moral judgments.
One might argue that under modern
conditions of ethical pluralism, a standard of universal assertibility
is illusory. But the alternative is unclear; it risks becoming
a door opener to moral skepticism. Accepting moral skepticism
is a choice, too, one that we cannot justify any better than
the quest for moral justification:
it implies that the stronger is "right," that is, we give up
any basis for communicatively rational practice. Without an
effort to give morality its genuine place in our notion of rationality,
strategic rationality is the only form of rationality that remains on the agenda. Without morality, no communicative
rationality.
From
the perspective of communicative rationality, our epoch's increasing
diversity of forms of life and value systems has paradoxical consequences indeed: the more
ethics becomes a personal matter, the more urgently we
need some interpersonally shared, moral standards that arguably deserve
general recognition, yet the less easily available are such arguments.
The more ethics faces us in the plural form, the more we need
a unifying moral standard. Thus the link between the moral and the rational of which Kant first
made us aware becomes more important than ever. With the rise of ethical pluralism, rationality
and moral universalism move closer together.
Kant
is alive and well: we cannot think and act rationally
without some universal notion of right and wrong. To the
extent we can identify such a universal right or wrong, we can
employ it as a standard for judging and justifying our own actions
and those of others. That is, we gain a moral
principle –
a perspective that allows us to take a personal
moral stance. We have, then, no choice but confronting the question of moral justification.
How can we define and use some universal notion of right and
wrong to decide rationally between clashing normative claims?
To prepare us for discourse ethics, I find it useful to return
once more to Kant.
Moral
justification and the viewpoint of impartiality
Ever
since Kant,
the core idea of moral justification has been the pursuit of impartiality:
we can judge and justify our actions, Kant taught us, by asking whether they
treat all the people concerned equitably. We may ask,
in
particular, whether our actions treat everyone with equal respect for their personal
dignity,
integrity, and needs, which also means they do not instrumentalize some
people for the ends of others only. To the extent an action
lives up to this standard we can, following Kant, consider
it as being morally
tenable or "justified," or as we say in everyday language, as
"fair"
or "just." There are at least three ways in which
we may interpret
the meaning of this "justified" from an everyday perspective
– in terms of rationality (1), of intuition (2), and of mutually granted
freedom of judgment and will (3).
Re:
(1) – The
link to rationality The
concept of impartiality is important because it explains the
crucial nexus between the moral and the rational. Unlike other
ethical issues, questions of impartiality are of a strictly
intersubjective nature and for this reason also allow of intersubjective
deliberation and decision making. While we have no rational
basis to say that anyone's form of life is as such right
or wrong, we can very well examine whether that person's
actions live up to the moral requirement of considering the
concerns and interests of others in an impartial way. Kant's
solution to the problem of moral justification – the way he
ties the moral to the rational – rests on this ingenious uncoupling
of moral questions from ethical questions: only with
regard to the interpersonal criterion of impartiality can we
say that ethical positions are "right" or "wrong" and thus can be "justified"
at all. Unlike all other kinds of ethical questions, which allow
us to maintain a basically egocentric perspective, moral questions
demand that we take the perspectives of others and remain impartial
with respect to them; what is more, all the parties concerned
can see and examine for themselves whether the answers we give
to moral questions – the norms that guide our actions – are
indeed impartial. This
is what we mean when we speak of the
moral point of view (Baier, 1958): it is the viewpoint
of impartiality, as the only, and therefore universal, perspective
from which we can rationally argue and decide about conflicting normative
claims.
Re:
(2) – The
link to everyday intuition In
addition to allowing us to tie the moral to the rational, the
concept of impartiality has the advantage of remaining
close to our everyday intuition of what moral morality is all about:
moral justification is about
a just solution of conflicts.
A "just" solution, as we already noticed, is one that does equal "justice" to all the parties
concerned. It can be demonstrated to be equitable,
unbiased, fair,
neutral, not siding with or against anyone. It is a solution
that "every impartial spectator would
approve" (Smith, 1795, p. 78, cf. pp. 100 and 343)
and which for this reason may be argued universally.
Our
intuitive notion of impartiality is closely associated with
the methodological core idea of moral universalization
– the idea of universal arguability. Kant
builds on the intuitive character of a thus-understood moral
perspective when he takes it for granted that every ordinary citizen
of good will is indeed able to submit his maxims of action to the test
of moral universalization. The "categorical imperative"
depends on this basis in everyday intuition for unfolding its
moral force.
But
there is a second, related yet slightly different sense in which
the Kantian notion of moral universalism remains close to our
everyday intuition of what morality is all about. We have previously
referred to Strawson's (1974) analysis of the connection between
everyday moral experience and the web
of mutual expectations, of attitudes and feelings, on
which we depend for cooperative
practice in our everyday social lifeworld. It is when others disrupt this web and thereby undermine the basis
for cooperative practice that we experience moral indignation. Intuitively
we understand that they put their private
agenda first and thus claim for themselves an exception from
those attitudes of reciprocity and fairness on which we all
depend. It is the universalistic thrust of this "we all"
that makes the breach of the moral principle so outrageous.
We need not first attend a philosophy course to know that we all depend
on this one basic standard of integrity that we call moral behavior
– behaving towards others the way we could everyone else want to
behave towards us. Our indignation about those who violate this
standard tells us we know this, and so does our own bad conscience when we ourselves
violate the standard.
Re:
(3) – The
link to freedom For Kant, the ultimate basis
of moral justification lies in the idea of freedom, by which he means the autonomous
use of our reason free from external constraints. "By 'the
practical'," Kant (1787, B828) wrote in the Critique
of Pure Reason, "I understand everything that is possible
through freedom." If I want to act reasonably in the sense
of practical reason, I must want to be free and indeed, cannot
help but assume that I am indeed free. This is different from
the realm of theoretical and instrumental reason, in which I
need to observe and obey the laws of nature. As we have
said earlier (Ulrich, 2010a, p. 9f), practical reason is in this respect "stronger"
than theoretical reason. It is free to create its own laws or
principles, although it cannot of course ignore or violate the
rules of nature:
Although
moral principles of reason can indeed give rise to free actions,
they cannot give rise to laws of nature. Accordingly, it is
in their practical, meaning thereby their moral, employment,
that the principles of pure reason have objective reality. (Kant,
1787, B835f)
The
implication is that the moral principle is grounded in freedom
and cannot exist without it. I can act morally only inasmuch
as I am free. The basic mood of morality is "I will,"
not "I must." This holds true also for the way I treat
other people: I cannot consider others as rational and
morally responsible persons unless they can judge and
act freely. I must thus make every effort I can to support their
free exercise of reason. There is something unconditional about this link
between a person's inner and outer freedom of judgment and her ability
to take a moral stance. As human beings, we can only build a
solid basis of mutual trust – that is, of mutual attribution of responsibility
as well as rationality in the sense of practical reason – by
granting one another such freedom, in the double sense of (a)
attributing to
each
other the good will of using whatever freedom we possess to
act according to the moral principle and (b), of also limiting
our own use of freedom accordingly, so that we do not take away
other people's freedom of moral judgment and action.
The moral principle is the only principle that can give "objective reality"
to the idea of freedom and thereby also to the free exercise
of practical reason (Kant, 1787, B836).
Hence,
as rational agents we cannot help but presuppose that
we are indeed free to act according to principles that we choose
ourselves, for the sole reason that we recognize them as being equally
just to all those concerned. To Kant, freedom in the sense of autonomy of judgment
and will is therefore the ultimate source of the moral force.
We cannot wish to act "with reason" and at the same
time deny our potential to judge and act autonomously. Because
we all have this potential, though perhaps to a varying degree
(depending on our moral maturity), we can indeed take a moral stance
– more than that, we recognize the absolute necessity of taking
a moral stance, as any other stance undermines the very foundation of the free use
of reason. As Kant concluded from his inquiry into the source
of the moral force in the Groundwork of the Metaphysic of
Morals:
Thus
the question "How is a categorical imperative possible?"
can be answered inasmuch as we can define the one presupposition
that makes it possible: the idea of freedom. The fact
that we can understand the unavoidability of this presupposition
is quite sufficient for the practical employment of reason,
that is, for convincing us of the validity of the imperative
and of the moral principle in which it is grounded. We cannot
hope to prove its validity any further, this is beyond human
reason; but we can understand its consequence: we cannot
act reasonably without presupposing that we have free will,
and then acting accordingly. (Kant, 1786, B124; my considerably simplified
transl.)
More
precisely, we not only need to presuppose that we have free
will but also that others respect it. Conversely, we cannot
expect them to do so unless we respect their need for the free exercise of reason. There
is this core idea again, of reciprocity of respect and consideration,
which appears to be a universal element in all conceptions of
ethics across all cultures and epochs and which we also found
to lie at the bottom of Kant's principle of moral universalization
(cf. Ulrich, 2009b, pp. 15-21). To Kant, the moral idea
is indeed rooted in mutual
respect for the intrinsic freedom of will of all human beings.
This is why it translates into the methodological requirement
of moral universalization and why in addition it is so important for Kant to conceive of
a moral agent in terms of an autonomous, universally
good will.
Morality
within the bounds of reason: Kant's answer to ethical pluralism
In consequence of what we just said about the link between
morality and freedom as well as about the other two links,
it became necessary for Kant to emancipate not only the moral
agent but also the
moral idea itself from the traditional
bounds of local custom,
politics, and ethics (.e.g., concerning the notion of a virtuous
way of life) that Aristotle had still
taken for granted. The same holds true for the bounds of religion and
for the authority of the church, which medieval scholasticism had
put in the place of the Aristotelian polis. Instead,
Kant concluded, it was necessary to ground morality, along with
religion (two ideas that at his time were difficult to separate),
within
the bounds of reason alone:
So far as morality is based upon the conception of man as a free
agent who, just because he is free, binds himself through his reason to
unconditioned laws, it stands in need neither of the idea of another Being
over him, for him to apprehend his duty, nor of an incentive other than the
law itself.… [For] whatever does not originate in himself and his
own freedom in no way compensates for the deficiency of his morality. (Kant,
1794, p. 3, first two sentences of the Preface)
The circle closes: the roots of morality in mutually
granted freedom of will lead us back to the intrinsic link between
morality and reason.
Conclusion:
Kant's "categorical" moral universalism If we now ask:
How can we defend the moral principle and its universalistic
thrust against the tide of ethical
pluralism and relativism? then the answer has to lie in the
intrinsic connections of the moral idea to each of the three aspects
of morally justified practice that we have considered:
- Unconditional
respect for the autonomy and integrity of others:
We cannot expect others to act responsibly without attributing to
them the ability and will to act morally; accordingly,
we must not only respect but indeed promote the
autonomy and integrity of all those whom we want to
act morally.
- Our
ordinary moral intuition: We cannot
remain indifferent to the disruptions of the social
web of mutual attitudes to which our moral feelings
point; for such disruptions undermine the basis for cooperative
and rationally justified practice.
- The
moral roots of consistent reason and cogent argumentation:
We cannot disregard the moral principle – with its demand
that we do not exempt ourselves from what we expect
from others – except at the price of sooner or later
entangling ourselves in argumentative
contradictions, and thereby losing the advantage of having
reason on our side.
All
three requirements hold unconditionally or,
as Kant prefers to say, categorically. That
is, we cannot claim any exemption from them, say, by
referring to the particular situation at hand or to our particular form of life or cultural tradition.
If we do claim an exemption, we thereby undermine the only basis there is for moral
practice – unconditional respect for the moral stance of doing
equal justice to all. Therein consists, ultimately, the "justification" of the moral idea.
It is, as Kant
made clear, a justification of a practical (or as Habermas would
say, formal-pragmatic) rather than theoretical kind. We are
theoretically free to behave immorally; but practically, we cannot expect others to treat us with the respect and fairness on which all cooperative
practice depends unless we take the same moral stance towards
them. It is, as George
H. Mead (1934, p. 380f; cf. Ulrich, 2009b, pp. 31 and
35) said so well, "a practical impossibility."
The
first of the three conditions is most fundamental
to Kant. The other two are of a derivative or auxiliary nature only
but have the advantage of revealing themselves to all of us in everyday
practice. We can observe and experience them in everyday discussions among
friends, at work, in politics, in newspaper
articles, by listening to people in the street
or on the bus, and so on. No particular
philosophical sophistication is required to see that disregard
for them not only undermines
the experience of unimpaired subjectivity that carries cooperative
practice but also leads us into weak, because inconsistent, argumentative
positions; and furthermore, that this is so across all ethical or cultural
differences. And since in our supposedly rational epoch, we all like to
have reason on our side – no one likes to be convicted of lacking
rationality – I suspect that the third basis of justification,
the deep link between morality and rationality, may under current
"modern" conditions show itself to be the strongest. Practical evidence,
too, suggest that the moral roots of consistent reasoning and
cogent argumentation can actually move things on and induce
change towards more equitable conditions, if only we dare to
stand up and argue our moral concerns. The encouraging circumstance
is that moral concerns (unlike immoral ones!) do indeed lend themselves to consistent
reasoning and cogent argumentation.
The
example of "banking secrecy" In
our earlier, detailed review of Kant, in the Bimonthly
of March-April 2009, we found that Kant's notion
of morality translates into a
powerful standard of moral reasoning, one that is truly universal:
the requirement that when it comes to normative issues, we
reason and argue consistently. As an example, we briefly (only in a footnote) considered the current regulatory controversy in the worldwide
finance industry, and particularly the problem of "tax havens," that
is, countries or states that promote
their finance industry by protecting tax evasion and tax fraud
on the part of so-called offshore (i.e., non-resident) clients
(cf. Ulrich, 2009b, p. 35f, note 3). We are now better
prepared to understand what this example tells us about the
power of moral universalism.
The controversy
is not really, as the public discussion has it, about a clash
of different legal systems, some of which consider banking secrecy
as illegal and others (supposedly with equal right and legitimacy)
as legal. One major effect of banking secrecy is that it allows
and obliges a country's finance industry to maintain the
anonymity of its foreign clients so as to protect
them from ordinary taxation by their countries of residence. By
giving legal protection to secret banking, the countries concerned not
only provide a competitive advantage to their finance industry but also disregard the fiscal sovereignty of other countries, in
a way they could not wish these other countries to practice
it themselves. The controversy therefore is at heart about a business model that is not
capable of being universalized, and about the question of whether
any country has the right to protect such a business model at
the expense of other countries. The core question is a moral
rather than legal one, and that is why the proponents of banking
secrecy find themselves in an unsustainable argumentative position.
From
a Kantian perspective, the moral assessment of the situation
is clear. Elevating tax
evasion protected by "banking secrecy" to a national
business model violates the principle of moral universalization.
No
country can credibly protect this business model for its own
financial industry and at the same time expect that other countries do
not likewise serve
as tax heavens for its own taxpayers. Applying such double standards
means you do not have the argument of reciprocity on
your side. The argumentative position of
tax havens is accordingly
weak; in defending this business model, they constantly entangle
themselves in argumentative contradictions. Necessarily so,
as Kant makes us understand: morally deficient positions,
due to their wanting generalizability,
cannot be argued consistently.
Eurocentrism?
In
the light of such fundamental consequences regarding argumentative
consistency, and considering the underlying refusal of a cooperative
attitude (in the specific case, in matters of international fraud prevention) that causes
it, the frequent reproach of Eurocentrism leveled against Kantian
ethics – the suspicion that its ethos of moral universalism
conceals a profoundly "Western,"
Eurocentric view of morality – loses some of its clout. To be
sure, it can hardly be denied that Kant's thinking originates
in particular traditions such as the Judeo-Christian Occident
and the Protestant Ethos of 18th century Prussia, along with
the Enlightenment ideas that flourished in Europe under the
reign of Frederick the Great. Kant's language of duty and respect,
but also his vision of a worldwide moral community within which
we all recognize our shared humanity and from which we would
not exclude anyone,
certainly give evidence of such a background ethos. Even
so, we may assume that a philosopher of Kant's format
does not simply allow himself to be a prisoner of his upbringing.
As evidence we may cite the observation just made, that this
ethos translates into a requirement as general and powerful
as consistent reasoning, along with the hardly outdated requirement
of taking a cooperative attitude
at a worldwide level (in this case,
in international fraud prevention).
We may equally recall our earlier observation
that the ethics of reciprocity that underpins
the categorical imperative can be found in all cultures and epochs
(see Ulrich, 2009b, pp. 16-18, 21, and 27f). The point, to be
sure, is not that Kant's conception of a morality "within
the bounds of reason alone" can do without any background
ethos, whether it has a Eurocentric bent or not; the point
is that Kant makes us understand why, and how exactly, the ethos
of reciprocity that informs his moral standard of impartiality
is truly universal. Kant's conception of rational ethics is universal inasmuch as
it translates into a truly universal requirement of
cooperative practice, which we have just identified as
the requirement of "having the argument
of reciprocity on one's side."
A
last observation that I find interesting and relevant is this.
As
the example of banking secrecy illustrates, Kant's moral universalism is
far from representing
merely a case of abstract and idealistic moral theorizing. Quite the contrary, Mead's
earlier cited observation has practical clout:
"We cannot demand from others what
we refuse to respect. It is a practical impossibility." (Mead,
1934, p. 381)
To
put it differently: we cannot expect
others to respect us without acknowledging the principle of
moral universalization. Moral universalism is indeed a universal
element of rational ethics; it is an ideal, to be sure, but
one with practical clout.
Moral
universalism, or the public use of reason
Kant described the practical
clout of moral universalization in a second, equally forceful
way. Morally strong reasons, he
argued in the true spirit of an enlightened and open society,
must allow us to back normative
claims publicly. Sound moral reasons, not unlike sound
scientific reasons, are public reasons – we can cite
them at all times, teach them everywhere. What Kant (1784, A484; cf. 1787, B766f) describes
as a key condition of enlightenment in general, the public use of reason, is
also an important characteristic of moral argumentation in particular.
It
seems to me this concept offers
us yet another key to a solution of the problem of moral justification,
certainly under contemporary conditions.
Unless we want
to ignore or deny that ethical pluralism and multiculturalism
have become part of modern life, need we not ultimately
regard publicly defensible reasons as universally
defensible reasons – reasons that we may invoke across all
ethical, cultural and ideological differences and thus could
in principle defend (and teach) universally. So much appears
to be clear: in a multicultural world, moral claims cannot
hope to be widely (let alone universally) acceptable unless
they are universal in the positive sense of lending themselves
to public employment in communicative practice, everywhere,
anytime. The price to pay, given ethical pluralism, is equally
clear: public reasons must also be universal in the negative sense of presupposing
a bare
minimum of shared normativity – the reverse side of the grounding
of morality within the bounds of reason, which explains the
formal and procedural rather than substantive and normative
nature of all rational ethics.
Summary:
Kant's moral universalism We have characterized
the thrust of Kant's moral universalism by means of five characteristics,
each of which implies a stance of inclusiveness (or non-exclusion)
towards all the parties concerned by a norm or normative claim:
- the
ethos of doing equal justice to all;
- the
viewpoint of impartiality, which alone allows
rational interpersonal argumentation about normative
claims and ethical clashes ;
- the
practical
impossibility of denying the moral point of view, due
to its intrinsic nexus with rationality and consistent reasoning
as well as to the social web
of mutual expectations, attitudes, and feelings (e.g., mutual
respect and trust) on
which all
cooperative
practice depends;
-
the need for grounding morality within the bounds of reason
alone, that is, with a minimum of normative presuppositions
(so as to be universally applicable) and independent of external sources of authority or
power (so as to preserve reason's integrity); and
- the affinity of
moral argumentation with the public use of reason.
Apart
from their universalistic implications, these five features
have one important aspect in common: they all point
to the need for a communicative turn of ethics.
Moral universalism
today: Habermas Since Kant did not have available at his time a philosophical
framework that would have allowed him to take the communicative
turn, he had no option but to find a way of capturing
the communicative implications of the moral point of view in
the traditional terms of a philosophy of consciousness, which
is exactly what the categorical imperative achieved.
But with the emergence of language analysis and discourse theory,
the situation has changed. There is no need any more to translate
the universalistic thrust of Kant's moral reasoning into a monological
"exercise of abstraction" (Habermas, 1993b, p. 24). We now have the theoretical
means to reformulate Kant's insights in terms that may better
equip us for dealing with the key challenge that all ethical
reflection faces today, the problem of ethical pluralism.
A
new philosophical modesty At
the same time, a recasting of moral theory in communicative
terms offers us a chance to relieve philosophy from the traditional,
but elitist, role of an arbiter of (moral or scientific) judgment
and instead to give it a more modest, but more credible, role.
Habermas (1990d, pp. 4 and 15) once described this new role
with
the image of philosophy as interpreter and "stand-in"
(Platzhalter) rather than "usher" (Platzanweiser).
That is, moral theory is no longer the authority that informs
practical agents about the right way to act (i.e., proper norms
of action); instead, it is now the task of moral
theory to put practical agents in a situation of participants, in
which they themselves can find out together what is the right thing to
do. We find it quite normal today that epistemology and philosophy of
science, for example, no longer
inform us about the phenomena and laws of nature but only clear
the ground for scientific practice to do its job of research
and theorizing in a self-critical manner; in much the same
way, I believe, we must learn to entrust moral judgment to philosophically
informed practice, rather than directly to philosophy.
Five
discursive equivalents of Kant's moral universalism
We
may then understand the communicative turn of rational ethics as a new
attempt, with the philosophical means of our epoch, to breath
life into the five Kantian conjectures that we associated above
with Kant's moral universalism.
Note that I do not follow Habermas' account of discourse ethics
here but rather "translate" his intent, as I pick
it up from various passages in his writings (to which I am going
to refer) into what we might
call five discursive equivalents of Kant's moral universalism:
- The
ethos of doing equal justice to all: Since "modern
life is characterized by a plurality of forms of life
and rival value convictions" (Habermas, 1993b,
p. 22), the central task of morality becomes one
of helping us to settle ethical clashes argumentatively.
Even more than at Kant's time we need to recognize today
that "the
peculiarly moral problematic detaches itself from the
egocentric (or ethnocentric) perspective of each individual's
(or our) way of life and demands that interpersonal
conflicts be judged from the standpoint of what all
could will in common." (Habermas, 1993b, p. 24)
The implication is moral universalism: moral
arguments either do justice to all, or they are not
moral arguments at all.
- The
viewpoint of impartiality is still the only perspective
from which we can rationally assess normative claims
and ethical clashes, except that the process of assessment
must now live up to the requirements of rational interpersonal
argumentation rather than just consistent personal reasoning.
Accordingly, moral justification becomes a matter of
argumentatively secured consensus rather than of individual
ethical self-reflection. Moral theory thus becomes the
task of reconstructing Kant's analysis of "the
conditions for making impartial judgments of practical
questions, judgments based solely on reasons" in
the terms of rational discourse rather than of
transcendental philosophy (Habermas, 1990a, p. 42,
cf. 1990d, p. 196).
- The
practical clout of moral reasoning: If we want to find a credible
basis for lived morality today, we cannot leave its justification
to moral theory alone but must somehow embed it in moral practice itself.
Moral insight must be conceived as the outcome of a
practical process, rather than the knowledge
of philosophers. Consequently, moral universalization
must now be conceived from a participant's rather
than an observer's perspective (Habermas, 1993b, pp. 22-24,
with references to Williams, 1985). The primary task
of moral theory then consists in a "clarification
of the conditions under which the participants could
find a rational answer for themselves." (Habermas,
1993b, p. 24)
- The
minimal normative core of moral reasoning: To make
sure moral argumentation does justice to the ethical
pluralism of our age, we
must restrict its normative basis to an absolute minimum
– to an ethical core that can count as impartial or neutral
in the sense that across all individual forms of life
and cultures, everyone who means to argue morally cannot
help but share this minimal normative basis. The telos
of mutual understanding (Habermas, 1984, p. 287;
1985, p. 173)
and the general pragmatic presuppositions
of discourse (e.g., 1984, pp. 25 and 34; 1998, p. 44)
amount for Habermas to such a minimal and culturally neutral,
normative core.
- The
public employment of moral reasoning:
Whatever reasons we may want to rely on in practice,
they can only avoid the suspicion of pursuing particular interests,
at the expense of a suppression of generalizable interests
(Habermas, 1973, pp. 111-116), if they are public reasons,
that is, can be defended publicly. For Kant, publicity
is the one principle that can make politics converge with
morality (Habermas, 1989, pp. 102-117, esp. 105-108). Accordingly, it
is clear for Habermas that well-understood moral
theory should aim at the public use of reason; it should
help us make sure that our
moral claims (or more accurately, the reasons we advance
in their support) hold good publicly. The requirements of
formal pragmatics, in particular the requirements of
open access and of equal argumentative chances for all, offer
themselves to this end: we may understand them as
aiming to make sure that rationally motivated consensus
is effectively based on public reasons. I am inclined
to suggest that we might indeed understand all of Habermas' work
– from his early work on the "public sphere"
via his social theory (the theory of "communicative
action") and moral theory ("discourse ethics")
to his legal and political philosophy ("deliberative
democracy") – as a relentless search for a philosophy
of
public reason.
Some
final conjectures I
find it stimulating indeed to identify such close parallels
between what I take to be some of the basic ideas of discourse ethics and
some corresponding ideas in Kant's conception of rational ethics,
especially since the latter are among those conjectures in
Kant's work that I consider most relevant to the aim of promoting reflective professional practice.
It should be clear, at the same time, that I do not mean to play
down the differences
that separate discourse ethics and Kant's moral theory.
I am thinking, for example, of the way Habermas (1979b, 1990b) links
cognitive ethics to Kohlberg's (1981, 1984) research into the
stages of moral development and socialization (a topic with
which we will deal a little more in the main essay on discourse
ethics that I am currently preparing), or of his partial shift from deontological to consequentialist
ethics
(which, as I have suggested above, at bottom includes a teleological
element). However, despite such differences, our current focus is on the theoretical development that takes
us from Kant's "monological" to a "discursive"
conception of the moral point of view. To this end, I find it useful
to regard the differences in question as methodological consequences,
rather than presuppositions, of the communicative turn.
As
to the latter – there are of course differing presuppositions that separate discourse ethics from Kant's
moral philosophy – perhaps the most essential difference is one of motives. Kant's
basic
motive of promoting the "good will" of
agents was still rather close to the Aristotelian quest for
clarifying the virtues of thought and character that should enable us to become good and happy persons;
by contrast, the basic motive behind discourse ethics is quite clearly the quest
for a communicative rationalization of society. This is why
discourse ethics, unlike Kant's approach, is closely linked
to social theory, argumentation theory, and political theory.
Discourse ethics is to be seen as an integral part of a more comprehensive effort,
the aim of which is to explore the implications of the quest for a
communicative
rationalization of society under
contemporary conditions of value pluralism and moral skepticism.
Subsequently to discussing discourse ethics, we will therefore
also briefly consider the roles of deliberative democracy and
of critical social science in this quest.
In
an interview of 1990 under the title "Morality, society, and ethics,"
I find a passage in which Habermas (1993d) sums up his motives
in words that we can now easily relate to the above-mentioned
Kantian conjectures:
Under
modern conditions, philosophy can no longer stand in judgment
over the multiplicity of individual life projects and collective
forms of life, and how one lives one's life becomes the sole
responsibility of socialized individuals themselves and must
be judged from the participant perspective. Hence, what is capable
of commanding universal assent becomes restricted to the procedure
of rational will formation. […] Even in answering questions
of direct practical relevance, convincing reasons can no longer
appeal to the authority of unquestioned traditions. If we do
not want to settle questions concerning the normative regulation
of our everyday coexistence by open or covert force – by coercion,
influence, or the power of the stronger interest – but
by the unforced conviction of a rationally motivated agreement,
then we must concentrate on those questions that are amenable
to impartial judgment. (Habermas, 1993d, p. 150)
The
common denominator of all these requirements is a concern for inclusiveness,
a moral intuition that for Habermas (as well as for Kant) translates methodologically
into moral universalism. Let us, at the end of this long exploration,
give the final word to Habermas and quote a somewhat longer
extract from The Inclusion of the Other in which he
sums up some of his rather nuanced
core conjectures. My hope at this stage must
be that the reader may find this quote repetitious; in other words,
that the reader will recognize in these words much of what we
have been exploring together in this essay.
I
proceed on the assumption that the participants do not wish
to resolve their conflicts through violence, or even compromise,
but through communication. Thus their initial impulse is to
engage in deliberation and work out a shared ethical
self-understanding on a secular basis. But given the differentiated
forms of life characteristic of pluralistic societies, such
an effort is doomed to failure. The participants will soon realize
that the critical appropriation of their strong evaluations
leads to competing conceptions of the good. Let us assume that
they nevertheless remain resolved to engage in deliberation
and not to fall back on a mere modus vivendi as a substitute
for the threatened moral way of life. In
the absence of a substantive agreement on particular norms,
the participants must now rely on the "neutral"
fact that each of them participates in some communicative
form of life which is structured by linguistically mediated
understanding. Since communicative processes and forms of life
have certain structural features in common, they could ask themselves
whether these features harbor normative contents that could
provide a basis for shared orientations. Taking this as a clue
[they will see] that morality derives a genuine meaning,
independent of the various conceptions of the good, from the
form and perspectival structure of unimpaired intersubjective
socialization.
[To be sure] traditionally established
obligations rooted in communicative action do not of
themselves reach beyond the limits of family, the tribe, the
city, or the nation. However, the reflexive form of communicative
action behaves differently: argumentation of its very
nature points beyond all particular forms of life. For in
the pragmatic presuppositions of rational discourse and deliberation
the normative content of the implicit assumptions of communicative
action is generalized [and] extended to an inclusive community
that does not in principle exclude any subject capable of speech
and action who can make relevant contributions. This idea points
to a way out of the modern dilemma […]. As we have seen, the
participants can only draw on those features of a common practice
they already currently share. [….] The bottom line is that the
participants have all already entered into the cooperative enterprise
of rational discourse. (Habermas, 1998a, pp. 39-41; the italics
are mine)
Concluding
remarks
The
reader may wonder: What is the bottom line of this preparatory exploration of some of the basic aims and assumptions
of discourse ethics? Conforming to the exploratory character
of this essay,
it can offer no definitive conclusion, no assessment of discourse
ethics, just a short self-reflection as to the limitations
of my own present effort, considering where we stand and where we go.
Argumentative
buds and clouds In this and the previous Bimonthly, I
have invited my readers
to look over my shoulder while
I am preparing to write on a difficult topic. I hope
readers will pardon the exploratory rather than systematic character
of these two essays. My attempt has been to help
readers and myself in becoming aware of some of the "argumentative
buds and clouds" (thus the motto of the previous Bimonthly's
picture) that we might want to consider on
our further way. I think we have indeed encountered some argumentative
"buds"
that promise to develop into relevant considerations and which
I will therefore want to take up in the main essay, along with
some argumentative "clouds" that call for clarification
(e.g., regarding some basic terminological and methodological issues)
and for some alternative ideas (e.g., with a view to ensuring
practicability).
What's
ahead – some doubts and difficult questions We have not as yet discussed the
difficult problem of operationalizing discourse ethics. Is
it possible to translate Habermas' rather abstract theoretical conjectures into specific
principles or rules of moral argumentation, as a modern Ersatz for the categorical imperative as it were? We
will see in the next contribution to the "Reflections on
reflective practice" series that Habermas introduces two
such rules, the "principle of discourse ethics (D)"
and "the principle of universalization (U)." The first
is a misnomer in that the second is equally a principle of discourse
ethics, otherwise there would be no need for it. The second,
too,
is to some extent a misnomer, in that the name does not tell
us whether and in what way it differs from the form that Kant gave to the universalization principle
in his categorical imperative – just two hints at the kind of difficulties
that expect us, and at the job of critical assessment still
awaiting us. We will try to understand what they actually achieve and what they
don't achieve, and what kind of conclusions
we need to draw with a view to supporting ethical practice.
I
have to confess at this point that I am not a true believer.
I doubt whether discourse ethics as Habermas understands it
is
able to help us very much in grounding professional practice
ethically. I fear it is all too theoretical and idealizing in
nature; in particular, it seems to me it presupposes conditions
of rational argumentation and consensus about moral questions
that are beyond what we can hope to achieve in real-world practice.
I fear, therefore, that it is bound to remain a piece of philosophy
of practice rather than being able to become a piece
of philosophy in practice, and thereby ultimately risks
missing the genuinely practical aim of "practical"
philosophy.
Precisely
because I have these doubts, I have focused so far on
exploring some of the main arguments in favor of discourse ethics, before
trying to assess it and to assign it an adequate
place in the quest for reflective professional practice. In
particular, I have tried as much as I could to strengthen its
case for moral universalism, despite some serious doubts regarding
the chances for putting moral universalization into practice.
Criticism
is meaningless and unproductive unless it is based on a previous sincere
attempt to understand, and even strengthen, the case
for the ideas at issue. In any case, there is much we can learn from discourse
ethics as a philosophy of practice, regardless of whether
in the end it yields a practicable framework for philosophy
in practice, that is, for lived professional ethics.
What
have we learned? We
may summarize some of the main points with which we have familiarized
ourselves as follows.
- Discourse
ethics focuses on the specific part of ethics made up
by moral questions. It is a piece of moral theory.
rather than a general – and "realistic"– model for practical
discourse.
- More
specifically, discourse ethics is an attempt to explain
the "moral point of view" in the discursive
terms of formal pragmatics. It is a theory
of moral discourse. Conforming to its theoretical
purpose, it tries to explain the discursive conditions that in
principle would allow us to justify moral claims, which
is not the same as telling us how these conditions might
be realized in practice.
- Moral
discourse is about dealing reasonably with ethical clashes, that
is, with conflicts between different notions of
the good and conforming courses of action.
- The
basic idea of discourse ethics in dealing with
ethical clashes is that to the
extent we can agree with others about disputed
norms or principles of action as a result of rationally
motivated discourse that is open to all those concerned,
we have good reason or grounds to expect all the parties concerned to share
these agreed-upon norms, and in that sense to consider
them as morally justified. Moral justification amounts to
moral universalization.
- Accordingly,
it is useful to understand discourse ethics as a special
theory of argumentation within the framework of
formal pragmatics; that is, a special application of
the Toulmin-Habermas model of argumentation.
- Inasmuch
as discourse ethics attempts to clarify the argumentative
presuppositions of moral justifications, we may also
understand
it as a special presuppositional analysis within
the framework of formal pragmatics.
- The
specific presuppositions of moral discourse that discourse
ethics finds indispensable beyond and in addition to
the general pragmatic presuppositions of any rationally
motivated discourse are these:
- that moral questions
have a cognitive content, that is, can be decided rationally;
- that
hidden in this cognitive content is a communicative kernel;
- that in view of modern conditions of ethical pluralism
and moral skepticism, the only kind of norms or principles that moral theory
can still credibly stipulate are of a formal and procedural
rather than substantial character;
- that contemporary ethics should
enlarge
Kant's deontological focus on the moral duties of a universally
good will with a pragmatic focus on consequences
and their moral tenability; and finally,
- that the central
idea we need to
salvage from Kantian ethics is its universalist stance,
according to which moral norms and principles either hold universally
(and hence, publicly) or are no moral norms or principles at all.
- In
consequence of all these considerations, the moral
point of view may be defined as the viewpoint of
impartiality, which in turn emerges as the only specifically moral
perspective from which we can rationally assess normative
claims and ethical clashes. Discourse ethics, then,
is a moral theory that explains what the viewpoint of
impartiality means in the argumentation-theoretical
terms of formal pragmatics.
|
For a hyperlinked overview of all issues
of "Ulrich's Bimonthly" and the previous "Picture of the
Month" series,
see the site map
PDF file
Note:
This is the second half of an exploratory essay in preparation
of the announced
third part of my introduction to the practical philosophy of
Habermas, within the current "Reflections on reflective practice" series.
|
|
References
Alexy,
R. (1978). Theorie der juristischen Argumentation: Die
Theorie des rationalen Diskurses als Theorie der juristischen
Begründung. Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp (English
transl.: A Theory of Legal Argumentation: The Theory of Rational
Discourse as Theory of Legal Justification,
Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press, 1989).
Alexy,
R. (1990). A theory of practical discourse. In Benhabib and
Dallmayr (1990), pp. 151-190.
Apel,
K.O. (1972). The a priori of communication and the foundation of
the humanities. Man and World, 5,
pp. 3-37. Partly reprinted in F.R. Dallmayr and T.A. McCarthy, eds., Understanding and Social Inquiry,
University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, Indianapolis, and London, UK, pp.
292-315.
Apel, K.O. (1973). Transformation der Philosophie, 2
vols., Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp (Engl. transl.:
Towards a Transformation of Philosophy, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1980).
Apel, K.O. (1975).
The a priori of the communicative community and the foundations of ethics.
In K.-O.Apel, Towards a Transformation of Philosophy, Vol.
2, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul,
pp. 225-300 (German
orig.: Das Apriori der Kommunikationsgemeinschaft und die Grundlagen
der Ethik, in Apel, 1973, Vol. 2, pp. 358-435).
Apel, K.O. (1981). Charles S.
Peirce: From Pragmatism to Pragmaticism. Amherst, MA: University
of Massachusetts Press (German orig.: Der Denkweg von
Charles S. Peirce, Eine Einführung in den amerikanischen Pragmatismus,
Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp, 1975).
Apel,
K.O. (1988). Diskurs und Verantwortung. Frankfurt am
Main, Germany: Suhrkamp.
Aristotle
(1976). The Ethics of Aristotle: The Nicomachean Ethics. Translated
by J.A.K. Thomson, Revised With Notes and Appendices
by H. Tredennick, Introduction and Bibliography by J. Barnes. London:
Penguin, 1976 (orig. London: Allen & Urwin, 1953).
Aristotle
(1985). Nicomachean Ethics. Translated, with Introduction,
Notes, and Glossary, by Terence Irwin. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.
Baier,
K. (1958). The Moral Point of View: A Rational Basis of Ethics.
Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Benhabib,
S. (1982). The methodological illusions of modern political
theory: the case of Rawls and Habermas. Neue Hefte für Philosophie,
21, No. 1, pp. 47-74.
Benhabib,
S., and Dallmayr, F. (eds.) (1990). The Communicative Ethics
Controversy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Dews,
P. (ed.) (1992). Autonomy & Solidarity: Interviews with Jurgen
Habermas. London: Verso, 2nd ed. (orig. 1986).
Günther,
K. (1988). Der Sinn für Angemessenheit: Anwendungsdiskurse
in Moral und Recht. Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp
(Engl. transl.: The Sense of Appropriateness: Discourses
of Application in Morality and Law, Albany, NY: State University
of New York Press, 1993).
Habermas,
J. (1973). Theory and Practice. Boston, MA:
Beacon Press.
Habermas,
J. (1975). Legitimation Crisis. Boston, MA: Beacon Press.
Habermas,
J. (1979a). What is universal pragmatics? In J. Habermas, Communication
and the Evolution of Society, Boston, MA: Beacon Press, pp.
1-68 (text) and 208-219 (notes).
Habermas,
J. (1979b). Moral development and ego identity. In J. Habermas, Communication
and the Evolution of Society, Boston, MA: Beacon Press, pp.
69-94 (text) and 219-222 (notes).
Habermas,
J. (1984). The Theory of Communicative Action. Vol. 1: Reason
and the Rationalization of Society. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.
Habermas,
J. (1985) Dialektik der Rationalisierung, in J. Habermas, Die
Neue Unübersichtlichkeit, Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp,
pp. 167-212. Orig. published as "Dialektik der Rationalisierung:
Jürgen Habermas im Gespräch mit Axel Honneth, Eberhard Knödler-Bonte
und Arno Widmann" in Aesthetik und Kommunikation,
No. 45/46, 1981. Engl. transl.: The dialectics of rationalization:
an interview with Jurgen Habermas, Telos, 49, Fall Issue,
1981; reprinted in Dew (1992), pp. 95-130.
Habermas,
J. (1989). The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere:
An Inquiry into a Category of Bourgeois Society. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press (orig.: Strukturwandel der Öffentlichkeit:
Untersuchungen zu einer Kategorie der bürgerlichen Gesellschaft,
Darmstadt, Germany: Luchterhand, 1962).
Habermas,
J. (1990). Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action.
Cambridge, UK: Polity Press (orig.: Moralbewusstsein und kommunikatives
Handeln, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1983).
Habermas,
J. (1990a). Discourse
ethics: notes on a program of philosophical justification.
In Habermas (1990), pp. 43-115 (orig.: Diskursethik,
Notizen zu einem Begründungs-programm, in J. Habermas, Moralbewusstsein
und kommunikatives Handeln, Frankfurt am Main, Germany:
Suhrkamp, 1983a, pp.53-125).
Habermas,
J. (1990b). Moral consciousness and communicative action. In
Habermas (1990), pp. 116-194 (orig.: Moralbewusstsein und kommunikatives
Handeln, in J. Habermas, Moralbewusstsein
und kommunikatives Handeln, Frankfurt am Main, Germany:
Suhrkamp, 1983a, pp.127-206).
Habermas,
J. (1990c). Morality and ethical life: Does Hegel's critique
of Kant apply to discourse ethics? In Habermas (1990), pp. 195-215
(orig.: Treffen Hegels Einwände gegen Kant auch auf die Diskursethik
zu? in J. Habermas, Erläuterungen zur Diskursethik, Frankfurt
am Main: Suhrkamp, 1991, pp. 9-30).
Habermas,
J. (1990d). Philosophy as a stand-in and interpreter. In Habermas
(1990), pp. 1-20 (orig.: Die Philosophie als Platzhalter und
Interpret, in J. Habermas, Moralbewusstsein
und kommunikatives Handeln, Frankfurt am Main, Germany:
Suhrkamp, 1983a, pp. 9-28).
Habermas,
J. (1993). Justification and Application: Remarks on Discourse
Ethics.
Habermas,
J. (1993a). On the pragmatic, the ethical, and the moral employments
of practical reason. In Habermas (1993), pp. 1-17
(orig.: Vom pragmatischen, ethischen und moralischen Gebrauch
der praktischen Vernunft, in J. Habermas, Erläuterungen zur
Diskursethik, Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp 1991,pp. 100-118).
Habermas,
J. (1993b). Remarks on discourse ethics. In Habermas (1993),
pp. 19-111 (orig.: Erläuterungen zur Diskursethik,
in J. Habermas, Erläuterungen zur Diskursethik, Frankfurt
am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp 1991, pp. 119-226).
Habermas,
J. (1993c) Lawrence Kohlberg and neo-Aristotelianism. In Habermas (1993),
pp. 113-132 (orig.:Kawrence Kohlberg und der Neoaristotelianismus,
in J. Habermas, Erläuterungen zur Diskursethik, Frankfurt
am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp 1991, pp. 77-99).
Habermas,
J. (1993d). Morality, society, and ethics:
an interview with Torben Hviid Nielsen. In Habermas (1993),
pp. 147-176 (orig.: Diskursethik und Gesellschaftstheorie: ein
Interview mit T. Hviid Nielsen, in J. Habermas, Die nachholende
Revolution, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1990, pp. 114-145;
now also in Habermas, 2009, Vol. 3, pp. 141-178).
Habermas,
J. (1998). The
Inclusion of the Other: Studies in Political Theory. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Habermas,
J. (1998a). A genealogical analysis of the cognitive content
of morality. In Habermas (1998), Ch. 1, pp. 1-46 (orig.: Eine
genealogische Betrachtung zum kognitiven Gehalt der Moral, in
J. Habermas, Die Einbeziehung des Anderen: Studien zur politischen
Theorie, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1996, pp. 11-64).
Habermas,
J. (2003). Truth and Justification.
Boston, MA: MIT Press (orig.: Wahrheit und Rechtfertigung: Philosophische Aufsätze,
Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp, 1999, enlarged paperback ed.
2004. Note that the English edition of 2004, due to its being based on the
original 1999 ed., does not contain the two important chapters
2 and 5 of the enlarged German ed.).
Habermas,
J. (2003a). Rightness versus truth: on the sense of normative
validity in moral judgments and norms. In Habermas (2003), pp. 237-275 (orig.: Richtigkeit
versus Wahrheit, in J. Habermas, Wahrheit und Rechtfertigung,
Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp 2004, Ch. 7, pp. 299-346).
Habermas,
J. (2009). Philosophische Texte, Band 3:
Diskursethik. Frankfurt am Main, Germany:
Suhrkamp.
Habermas,
J. (2009a). Einleitung [Introduction]. In Habermas
(2009), pp.
9-30.
Hegel,
G.F.W. (1802). "Kritik an Kants Moralprinzip." In:
Über die wissenschaftlichen Behandlungsarten des Naturrechts,
seine Stelle in der praktischen Philosophie, und sein Verhältnis
zu den positiven Rechtswisenschaften. Kritisches Journal
für Philosophie, 2, No. 2, pp. 1-88, and No. 3,
pp. 1-34. The Section "Kritik an Kants Moralprinzip"
appears in No. 2, pp. 35-43; reprinted under the title
"Aus dem Naturrechtsaufsatz: Kritik an Kants Moralprinzip"
in R. Bittner and K. Cramer (eds.), Materialien
zu Kants "Kritik der praktischen Vernunft," Frankfurt
am Main: Suhrkamp, 1975, pp. 327-332 (Engl. transl. of
the entire essay: Natural Law: The Scientific Ways of Treating Natural Law, Its
Place in Moral Philosophy, and Its Relation to the Positive Sciences, Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania Press,
1975).
Kant,
I. (1784). What is enlightenment? Orig.: Beantwortung der Frage:
Was ist Aufklärung? Berlinische Monatszeitschrift, VI,
December, pp. 481-494. Reprinted in: W. Weischedel (ed.):
Werkausgabe Vol. XI, Schriften zur Anthropologie, Geschichtsphilosophie,
Politik und Pädagogik 1, Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp
1977, pp. 51-61. English transl. in L.W. Beck
(ed.), Kant’s
Critique of Practical Reason and Other Writings in Moral Philosophy, Chicago, IL:
Chicago University Press, 1949, pp. 286-292. (Note:
References are to the pagination of the orig. text; translations
are my own. For a standard English translation, see, e.g., the Internet Modern History Sourcebook:
[HTML] http://www.fordham.edu/halsall/mod/kant-whatis.html
)
Kant,
I. (1786). Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals. 2nd ed.
[B] (1st ed. [A] 1785). Transl. by H.J. Paton. New York:
Harper Torchbooks, 1964. German orig.: Grundlegung zur Metaphysik
der Sitten, 1st ed. [A] and 2nd ed. [B], in: W. Weischedel
(ed.), Werkausgabe Vol. VII, Kritik der praktischen Vernunft,
Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten, Frankfurt am Main, Germany:
Suhrkamp, 1977 (orig. 1968), pp. 9-102.
Kant,
I. (1787). Critique of Pure Reason. 2nd ed. [B] (1st ed.
[A] 1781). Transl. by N.K. Smith. New York: St. Martin's Press,
1965 (orig. Macmillan, New York, 1929). German orig.: Kritik der
reinen Vernunft, 1st ed. [A] 1781, 2nd ed. [B] 1787, in: W. Weischedel
(ed.), Werkausgabe Vols. III and IV, Frankfurt am Main, Germany:
Suhrkamp 1977 (orig. 1968).
Kant,,
I. (1794). Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone.
2nd ed. [B] (1st ed. [A] 1793). Transl. by T.M. Greene and H.H.
Hudson, with a new essay "The ethical significance of Kant's
religion." New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1960 (orig. La
Salle, IL: Open Court, 1934). German
orig.: Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der blossen Vernunft,
in W. Weischedel (ed.), Werkausgabe Vol.
VIII, Die Metaphysik der Sitten, Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp,
1977, pp. 645-879.
Kohlberg,
L. (1981). Essays on Moral Development, Vol. 1: The Philosophy
of Moral Development – Moral Stages and the Idea of Justice. San Francisco: Harper &
Row.
Kohlberg,
L. (1984). Essays on Moral Development, Vol. 2: The Psychology
of Moral Development – The Nature and Validity of Moral Stages. San Francisco: Harper &
Row.
Lorenzen,
P., and Schwemmer, O. (1977). Konstruktive Logik, Ethik und
Wissenschafts-theorie. Mannheim, Germany: Bibliographisches
Institut.
MacIntyre,
A. (1981). After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory. London:
Duckworth, 2nd ed. 1985.
McCarthy,
T. (1978). The Critical Theory of Jürgen Habermas. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Mead,
G.H. (1934). Mind, Self, and Society from the Standpoint of a
Social Behaviorist. Ed. by C.W. Morris. Chicago, IL: University
of Chicago Press.
Moore,
G.E. (1903). Principia Ethica. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
University Press.. Electronic transcription: [HTML] http://fair-use.org/g-e-moore/principia-ethica
Rawls,
J. (1971). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Belknap/ Harvard
University Press.
Rorty,
R. (1979). Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press.
Silber, J.R. (1974). Procedural formalism
in Kant's ethics. Review of Metaphysics, 28, No. 2,
pp. 197-236.
Singer,
M. G. (1961). Generalization in Ethics. An Essay in the
Logic of Ethics, with the Rudiments of a System of Moral Philosophy.
New York: Knopf.
Smith,
A. (1795). The Theory of Moral Sentiments. New York: Cosimo Classics,
2007.
Strawson,
P. (1974). Freedom and Resentment. London: Methuen. New
ed. Oxon, UK: Routledge, 2008 (page references are to the
new ed.).
Toulmin,
S.E. (1970). An Examination of the Place of Reason in Ethics.
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press (orig. 1570).
Tugendhat,
E. (1984). Probleme der Ethik. Stuttgart, Germany: Reclam.
Tugendhat,
E. (1989). Zum Begriff und zur Begründung von Moral. In C. Bellut
and U. Müller-Schöll (eds.), Mensch und Moderne; Beiträge zur philosophischen Anthropologie und Gesellschaftskritik,
Würzburg, Germany: Königshausen & Neumann, pp. 145-163.
Ulrich,
W. (1983). Critical Heuristics of Social Planning: A New Approach
to Practical Philosophy. Bern, Switzerland: Haupt. Pb. reprint ed. New
York: Wiley, 1994.
Ulrich,
W. (1994). Can
we secure future-responsive management through systems thinking
and design? Interfaces,
24, No. 4,
1994, pp. 26-37. Rev. version, 20 March 2009,
in "A Tribute to C. West Churchman," Werner Ulrich's Home Page,
[HTML]
http://wulrich.com/frm.html [PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/ulrich_1994.pdf
Ulrich,
W. (2009a). Reflections on reflective practice (4/7): Philosophy
of practice and Aristotelian virtue ethics. Ulrich's
Bimonthly, January-February 2009. [HTML]
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_january2009.html [PDF] http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_january2009.pdf
Ulrich,
W. (2009b). Reflections on reflective practice (5/7): Practical reason
and rational ethics: Kant. Ulrich's
Bimonthly, March-April 2009. [HTML]
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_march2009.html [PDF] http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_march2009.pdf
Ulrich,
W. (2009c). Reading Habermas in the garden chair
(cloudspotter's
summer break). Ulrich's
Bimonthly, July-August 2009. [HTML] http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_july2009.html [PDF] http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_july2009.pdf
Ulrich,
W. (2009d). Reflections
on reflective practice (6a/7): Communicative
rationality and formal pragmatics – Habermas 1. Ulrich's
Bimonthly, September-October 2009. [HTML] http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_september2009.html [PDF] http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_september2009.pdf
Ulrich,
W. (2009e). Reflections
on reflective practice (6b/7): Argumentation theory and practical
discourse – Habermas 2. Ulrich's
Bimonthly, November-December 2009. [HTML] http://wulrich/bimonthly_november2009.html [PDF] http://wulrich/downloads/bimonthly_november2009.pdf
Ulrich,
W. (2010a). Exploring discourse ethics (1/2). Ulrich's
Bimonthly, March-April 2010. [HTML] http://wulrich/bimonthly_march2010.html [PDF] http://wulrich/downloads/bimonthly_march2010.pdf
Wellmer,
A. (1991). The Persistence of Modernity: Essays on Aesthetics,
Ethics, and Postmodernism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Williams,
B. (1985). Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Wimmer,
R. (1980). Universalisierung in der Ethik: Analyse, Kritik
und Rekonstruktion ethischer Rationalitätsansprüche. Frankfurt
am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp.
|
|