Werner Ulrich's Home Page:  Ulrich's Bimonthly

Formerly "Picture of the Month"

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

July-August 2017
If Systems Thinking is the Answer, What is the Question?
Discussions on Research Competence (Part 2/2)

   Ulrich's Bimonthly

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

Abstract  This is Part 2/2 of an essay on the nature of research practice that originates in discussions with students and professionals from various applied disciplines. For the Abstract, as well as the essay history and the suggested citation, see Part 1/1, which you will find in the Bimonthly of May-June, 2017.

 

Previous |

 Next

For a hyperlinked overview of all issues of "Ulrich's Bimonthly" and the previous "Picture of the Month" series, see the site map

PDF file

Note: This Bimonthly completes the revised and updated version of the two-part essay on the nature of research competence. For Part 1, see the previous Bimonthly of May-June, 2017. The PDF version, available through the link above, comes as an undivided, integral version of the essay.

 

 

 << Continued from Part 1/2

What Ought to Count as Knowledge?  Research is usually undertaken to increase knowledge. A typical dictionary definition explains that research is "to establish facts and reach new conclusions" (Concise Oxford Dictionary of Current English). This is not a bad definition. Counter to the frequent, often tacit identification of research with empirical research, the Oxford definition tells us that research requires two kinds of competencies:

  • observational skills to "establish facts," and
  • argumentative skills to "reach new conclusions."

The first kind of skills refers to the ideal of high-quality observations, that is, observations that are capable of generating valid statements of fact. This ideal is traditionally but rather inadequately designated "objectivity"; it requires our propositions or claims to possess observational qualities such as intersubjective transferability and controllability, repeatability over time, adequate precision, and clarity with respect to both the object and the method of observation.

The second kind of skills refers to the ideal of cogent reasoning, that is, processes of (individual) reflection and (intersubjective) argumentation that generate valid statements about the meaning (interpretation, justification, relevance) of observations. This ideal is traditionally designated "rationality"; it requires our propositions to possess communicative and argumentative qualities such as syntactic coherence, semantic comprehensibility, logical consistency with other statements, empirical content (truth), pragmatic relevance and normative legitimacy (rightness).

Both requirements raise important issues for the concept of research competence. How can we know whether we "really" know, that is, whether our observations are high-quality observations or not? And if we can assume that they are, how can we know whether we understand their meaning correctly and draw the "right" conclusions, that is, that we reason and argue correctly?

Competent observation and argumentation require one another  A particular difficulty with the two requirements is indeed that they are inseparable. This becomes obvious as soon as we consider the nature of the "facts" that quality observations are supposed to establish:

Facts are what statements (when true) state; they are not what statements are about [i.e., objects]. They are not, like things or happenings on the face of the globe, witnessed or heard or seen, broken or overturned, interrupted or prolonged, kicked, destroyed, mended or noisy. (Strawson, 1964, p. 38, cf. Ulrich, 1983, p. 132)

That is to say, facts are not to be confused with objects of experience; they cannot be experienced (they are statements rather than objects), just as objects of experience cannot be asserted (only statements can). Facts, because they are statements, need to be argued. Accordingly observational and argumentative competencies must go hand in hand; they are but two sides of one and the same coin. (Fig. 1)

Two dimensions of research competence

Fig. 1: Two dimensions of competence in systems thinking and research: observational and argumentative.

Each dimension entails specific validity claims, the redemption of which may, however, involve claims that refer to the other dimension.

Let us consider some of the specific requirements on each side of the coin. On the argumentative side, Habermas' (1979; 1984-87) well-known model of rational discourse gives us a framework for analyzing the difficult implications of the quest for compelling argumentation or, as he puts it, "communicative competence."

What makes a good argument? According to this model, a competent speaker would have to be able to justify (or "redeem," as Habermas likes to say) the following validity claims that all rationally motivated communication entails and which together amount to a "universal validity basis of speech":

  1. Comprehensibility: a claim that entails the obligation to express oneself so that the others can hear and understand the speaker; it cannot be redeemed discursively but merely through one's communicative behavior.
  2. Truth: a claim that entails the obligation to provide grounds for the empirical content of statements, through reference to quality observations and through theoretical discourse.
  3. Rightness: a claim that entails the obligation to provide justification for the normative content of statements, through reference to shared values (e.g., moral principles) and through practical discourse.
  4. Truthfulness: a claim that entails the obligation to redeem the expressive content of statements by proving oneself trustworthy, so that the others can trust in the sincerity of the speaker's expressed intentions; again this cannot be redeemed discursively but only through the consistency of the speaker's behavior with the expressed intentions.
    (adapted from Habermas, e.g., 1979, pp. 2-4, 63-68)

Since these validity claims are always raised simultaneously in all communication, whether explicitly or implicitly, it becomes apparent that a competent researcher must be prepared to substantiate statements of fact not only through credible reference to quality observations but also through theoretical and practical discourse, so as to convince those who doubt or contest the "facts" in question of the validity of their underlying, theoretical and normative presuppositions.

What makes a good observation?  Similar difficulties arise with the requirement of substantiating the quality of observations. Observations – or more precisely, observational statements – always depend on the construction of some sort of objects that can be observed and reported upon. Depending on the situation, these constructions may need to rely on different notions of what kinds of objects lend themselves to quality observations. A conventional notion of "objects" assumes that the objects of observation can be construed to be largely independent of the purposes of both the observer and the user of the generated knowledge. In such a conventional account, a claim to quality observations will entail the obligation to redeem at least the following requirements:

  1. Validity: the observation observes (or measures) what it is supposed to observe (or measure).
  2. Reliability: the observation can be repeated over time and provides (at least statistically) a stable result.
  3. Transferability: the observation can be repeated by other observers and in that sense proves to be observer-independent (a validity claim that is often subsumed under 2).
  4. Relevance: the observation provides (together with other observations) information that serves as a support for a statement of fact, or for an argument to the truth of some disputed fact.

The "Challenge of the User": Towards a richer construction of high-quality observations and arguments  Historically speaking, these or similar assumptions characterized the rise of the empirical sciences (especially the natural sciences) about three centuries ago. More recently, however, with the extension of scientifically motivated forms of inquiry to ever more areas of human concern, competent research increasingly faces the difficulty that contrary to the original assumptions, quality observations cannot be assumed to be independent of either the observer or the user or both. As for instance de Zeeuw (1996, pp. 2f and 19f /2001, pp. 1f and 25f) observes, science is now more and more faced with the challenge of the user, that is, the task of constructing quality observations so that they allow users to have a voice inside science. This is different from conventional science which, because of its underlying notion of non-constructed, observer- and user-independent objects, depends on the exclusion of users.

Typical examples are research efforts in the domains of therapy (e.g., psychiatry), social work and social planning (e.g., care for the elderly or fighting poverty), business management (e.g., organizational design, management consultancy), and public policy-making (e.g., policy analysis, evaluation research). "Patients," "clients," and "decision-makers" increasingly claim a voice in the making of the observations of concern to them, so that "diagnoses," "help" or "solutions" are not merely imposed upon them without considering their observations. What does it mean for a researcher to assure high-quality observations under such circumstances?

Three phases of science: expanding the reach of high-quality observation  De Zeeuw has discussed this issue extensively (e.g., 1992, 1995, 1996/2001, 2005). He distinguishes three notions of "objects" that allow quality observations responding to different circumstances (the examples are mine): non-constructed objects (e.g., the seemingly given, observer-independent objects of astronomy such as the celestial bodies and phenomena),7) constructed objects (e.g., groups such as "the poor" or "the upper class" as objects of the social sciences, or "systems" as objects of the systems sciences), and self-constructed objects (e.g., expressions of human intentionality as objects of study in social systems design, organizational analysis, environmental and social impact assessment, action research etc., where the construction of the objects to be observed is left to those who are concerned in the observations at issue, be it because they may be affected by them or because they may need them for learning how to achieve some purpose, or else because they may be able to contribute some specific points of view). These three notions of objects give rise to three developments of science which de Zeeuw calls "first-phase," "second-phase," and ‘third-phase" science.

If I understand de Zeeuw correctly,8) the constructed objects of second-phase science distinguish themselves from objects of first-phase science in that they depend on the observer's purpose (e.g., the improvement of some action or domain of practice); the self-constructed objects of third-phase science depend, moreover, on the full participation of all the users of the knowledge that is to be gained.

The emancipatory turn  The notion of competent research that I propose here and which is also contained in my work on critical heuristics (CSH), critical systems thinking (CST) for citizens, and critical pragmatism, is certainly sympathetic to the idea of combining the "challenge of the user" with an adequate notion of (objects of) high-quality observations, a notion of quality that – in my terms – would give a competent role to all those concerned in, or affected by, an inquiry. I thus quite agree with de Zeeuw (1996, p. 19; 2001, p. 24) when he refers to CSH as an example of a type of inquiry that focuses on "the need to give users in general a voice inside science," so as to overcome the conventional limitation of quality observations to objects that are constructed by researchers without the full participation of users. It should be noted clearly, however, that CSH aims beyond the instrumental purpose of improving the quality of "scientific" observations; it also aims at emancipating ordinary people from the situation of incompetence and dependency in which researchers and experts frequently put them in the name of science. It aims at the earlier-mentioned insight that what in our society counts as knowledge is always a question of what ought to count as knowledge, whence the issues of democratic participation and debate and of the role of citizenship in knowledge production become essential topics. That is why I find it important to associate the challenge of the user with the goal of allowing citizens (as well as researchers) to acquire a new competence in citizenship (Ulrich, 1995, 1996a, b, 1998b, 2000, 2012a).

Towards a New Symmetry of Critical Competence  For me, a fundamental source of such competence consists in learning to handle the boundary judgments that inevitably underpin all application of research and expertise. The crucial point is that when it comes to boundary judgments, researchers or experts have no in-principle advantage over ordinary citizens:

When an expert, by reference to his theoretical knowledge, defines "the problem" at hand or determines "the solution," he must always presuppose such boundary judgments. To define the problem means, in fact, to map the social reality (or the social system) to be dealt with; to determine the solution means to design a better social reality (or social system). And since every map or design depends on previous boundary judgments (or whole systems judgments) as to what is to be included in it and what is to belong to its environment, it is clear that no definition of "the problem" or "the solution" can be objectively justified by reference to theoretical knowledge. It can only be critically justified by reference to both the transparency of values and the consent of all the affected citizens.
    The first implication is trivial: no amount of expertise (theoretical knowledge) is ever sufficient for the expert to justify all the judgments on which his recommendations depend. When the discussion turns to the basic boundary judgments on which the exercise of expertise depends, the expert is no less a layman than are the affected citizens.
    The second implication is less trivial, in that it seems to contradict common sense: no expertise or theoretical knowledge is required to comprehend and to demonstrate that this is so. The necessity of boundary judgments can be intuitively grasped by every layman: since no one can include "everything" in his maps or designs, he cannot help presupposing some boundaries.… Anybody who is able to comprehend the [relevance of such] boundary judgments is also able to see through the dogmatic character of the expert's "objective necessities." (Ulrich, 1983, p. 306, italics original)

To be sure, experts are still needed to inform all those without special expertise in an issue at hand (and virtually all of us find themselves in this position most of the time) about the likely or possible consequences of different boundary assumptions, and thus about the options for efficacious action and resulting kinds of improvement, side-effects, and risks. But they have no privileged position when it comes to choosing among these options, and thus among the competing boundary judgments:

Experts may be able to contribute to the task of anticipating the practical consequences of alternative boundary judgments; but they cannot delegate to themselves the political act of sanctioning the normative content of these consequences. (Ulrich, 1983, p. 308)

This explains why professionals, counter to what one might expect, have no natural advantage over ordinary citizens with respect to boundary judgments. There is, in principle, a symmetry of critical competence (Ulrich, 1993, p. 604) between citizens and professionals, as both sides have an equal chance of handling boundary questions in self-reflective and transparent ways (for fuller accounts, see Ulrich, 1983, entire ch. 5, esp. pp. 305-310; 1987, p. 281f; 1993, pp. 599-605, 2000, p. 254). The need for a careful and open handling of boundary judgments thus translates into a new skill of boundary critique, a skill that in principle is available equally to citizens and to professionals as it does not depend on any special expertise that would be beyond the comprehension of ordinary people. Once we understand this implication, our concept of high-quality observation of situations will change, as will also our concept of compelling argumentation.

Limitations of Science Theory and Research Methodology  But of course, giving users a more competent voice within research does not answer all the questions raised by the search for valid and relevant "findings and conclusions." The deeper reason for this is that we are dealing with an ideal. A competent researcher will always endeavor to make progress toward it, while never assuming that he or she has attained it.

Wanting theories of truth and rationality  We do not currently have, and chances are we will never have, operational theories of "true" knowledge and "rational" argumentation. Given this situation, along with the ideal character of the quest for scientific validation, we should not expect philosophers of science and theorists of research methodology, either, to come up with safe and sufficient guidelines, not any more than practicing researchers.

As far as the problem of ensuring high-quality observations is concerned, the basis for such guidelines would have to be some sort of a practicable correspondence theory of truth. Such a theory would have to explain how we can establish a "true" relationship – a stable kind of "correspondence" – between statements of fact and reality. But then, "reality" is not accessible except through the statements of observers who, apart from being human and thus imperfect observers, construct it dependent on their particular views and interests and corresponding boundaries of concern (i.e., boundary judgments). It is thus clear that such a theory is basically impossible. The ideal – if indeed it is a proper ideal – will remain just that, a mere ideal.

Similarly, with regard to the problem of securing compelling argumentation, the necessary basis would consist in a practicable theory of "rationally" argued consensus. Such a discourse theory of rationality would have to explain how a consensus can be shown to be justified rather than merely factual, that is, what kind of arguments are necessary to support it and what conditions could ideally warrant these arguments. But as we have learned from Habermas' (1979) analysis of the "ideal speech situation," such a theory cannot make those ideal conditions real. This is a topic that I consider essential for developing our contemporary concept of science so as to meet the challenge of the user, but it leads far beyond the scope of the present, introductory essay. Interested readers can find some of my efforts to come to terms with the difficult path to communicative rationality elsewhere (e.g., Ulrich, 1983, Ch. 2; 2009a, b; 2013a)

Insofar as the methods of natural science appear to provide a proven tool for ensuring scientific progress, many natural scientists may disregard the lack of philosophical grounding without worrying too much. The social sciences and the applied disciplines are in a less comfortable position, however. The way they deal with these issues is bound to affect the findings and conclusions they will be able to establish. Applied researchers need to be especially careful as to what their quest for competence means and in what respects it can or cannot be grounded epistemologically and methodologically. As students of the applied disciplines, how can you square the circle and hope to become a competent researcher or professional despite the lack of sufficient epistemological and methodological guidelines?

Methodological Pluralism  The unavailability of a satisfactory answer is probably responsible for the postmodern rise of pluralism in epistemological and methodological thought, sometimes also called "methodological complementarism." Since there is no single theoretical and methodological framework that would be best for all research tasks and circumstances, so goes the reasoning, the value of research depends on careful choice and combination of methodologies and conforming methods. Accordingly, meta-level frameworks for selecting proper research approaches need to be developed to support sound practice. In the management sciences, for example, this so-called "methodology choice" approach has been heralded particularly in the writings of Jackson (e.g., 1987, 1990, 1991, 1997, 1999), Midgley (e.g., 1992, 1997), and Mingers (Mingers and Brocklesby, 1996; Mingers and Gill, 1997). In different ways and partly critical of this meta-level approach, which raises unsolved theoretical problems of its own, methodological pluralism or complementarism also informs the work of other authors in the field, including my own work (e.g., Linstone, 1984 and 1989; Oliga, 1988; Ormerod, 1997; Ulrich, 1988, 2003; 2012c, d, e, 2013b, 2017; White and Taket, 1997).

But of course, the call for epistemological and methodological pluralism, justified as it is by the lack of satisfactory theories of knowledge and of rationality, merely makes a virtue of necessity. It cannot conceal the fact that if by "competent" research we mean a form of inquiry that would give us sufficient reasons to claim the validity of our findings and conclusions, the quest for competence in research remains chimerical. The methodology choice approach, as we already found above in a different context (discussing the mistaken idea that theoretically grounded methods can justify practice), just doesn't carry far enough.

The ongoing quest for good practice  For a tenable practice of research, we still need additional guidelines. Two sources of guidelines have become particularly important for my understanding of competence in research:

(a) Rethinking the relationship of theory and practice: Instead of seeking a basis for claims to knowledge and rationality in the scientific qualities of research alone, we might be better advised to seek to base them in a proper integration of research and practice. The issue that comes up here is the precise model for mediating theory and practice, or science and politics, that should underpin our understanding of competence in applied research.

(b) The critical turn of practice: Instead of seeking to validate claims to knowledge and rationality positively, in the sense of ultimately sufficient justification, we might be better advised to defend them critically only, by renouncing the quest for sufficient justification in favor of the more realistic quest for a sufficient critique, that is, for a systematic effort of laying open justification deficits. The issue here is what in my writings I describe as the "critical turn" (or, in some more specific contexts, also as the "critically-heuristic," "critically-discursive," and "critically-normative" turns) of our notions of competence, knowledge, science, rationality, good practice, and so on, and as the consequent quest for an at least critical solution to the problem of practical reason, along with the critical significance of the systems idea for such a solution.9)

Mediating theory and practice  Ever since the rise of science, there has been a hope that political practice, that is, the use of power, could be enlightened by science. At the bottom of this issue lies the question of the proper relationship between science and society, between technically exploitable knowledge and normative-practical understanding (and improvement) of the social life-world, between "theory" and "practice."10)

From Aristotelian praxis to decisionism  Until the rise of science, Aristotle's (1981, 1985) view of rational practice (praxis) as a non-scientific domain that was to be grounded in the ethos of the polis and in the model of proper conduct or "excellence" (arete) provided by virtuous individuals, was generally accepted. The crucial link between reason and practice consisted for Aristotle in his belief that "we cannot be intelligent without being good" (1985, Book VI, Ch. 12). Virtues of character and of thought were the human qualities that mattered most for proper praxis, much more than reliance on theoretical knowledge (theoria) and technical skills (poiesis). Interestingly, these virtues were not simply given to individuals but were the result of hard work and of a persistent, life-long quest for excellence or, as we say in this essay, for competence. Modern as this Aristotelian concept is, there is a basic difference to the quest for competence that inspires the present essay: Aristotle saw the task and virtue of excellence (or competence) in its supporting the traditioned, conventional way of life of the community and thus would hardly have expected it to pursue a critical or even emancipatory intent along the lines of "boundary critique."

For some one and a half millennia after Aristotle, this conventionalist, but ethically grounded notion of rational practice prevailed. The alternative idea of grounding it in science and research did not arise before the modern age. It was the English political philosopher Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679) who in the middle of the seventeenth century proposed a first design for the scientization of politics. His insight was that practical issues raise questions that are scientifically accessible insofar as they require theoretical or technical knowledge. Once these theoretical or technical questions had been identified, the remaining questions would then properly remain inaccessible to science as they required genuinely normative, subjective decisions that lie beyond rationalization through theory or technique. Thus decisionism was born, the doctrine that practical questions allow of scientific rationalization as far as they involve the choice of means; for the rest, they can only be settled through the (legitimate) use of power. Auctoritas, non veritas, facet legem, became Hobbes' motto: "Power rather than truth makes the law." The limited function of science, then, consists in informing those in a situation of (legitimate) power about the proper choice of means for their ends, according to the guideline: "Knowledge serves power."

From the decisionistic to the technocratic model  For the Enlightenment thinkers, this could not be the last word on the matter. Veritas, non auctoritas, facet legem, that is, "Truth rather than power makes the law," was postulated by the French Enlightenment philosopher Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712-1778) as a counterpoint against Hobbes. It was to take nearly two centuries for Rousseau's postulate to acquire some empirical content (descriptive validity) in addition to its normative content. The growth of administrative and scientific tools for rationalizing decisions, exemplified by the development of computers, decision theory, and systems analysis in the middle of the twentieth century, led to a partial reversal of the relationship between the politician and the expert or researcher: the researcher's understanding of real-world issues now increasingly tends to determine the need and criteria for political action. One need only think of environmental issues to realize how much science nowadays defines the factual constraints to which politicians must succumb.

What remains to politics, then, is paradoxically the choice of the means that are capable of responding to the needs that have been defined by the experts. As a former chief evaluator in the public sector, I have often experienced this peculiar reversal of roles: I was expected to come up with "scientific" findings and conclusions as to what needed to be done, so that the politician could then justify his chosen measures (or his inactivity) by referring to the recommendations of the evaluation researcher. The danger is that the genuine function of politics, to ensure legitimate decisions on issues of collective concern, is in effect delegated to researchers who, because they hold no political mandate, are not democratically accountable.

To the extent that this reversal of roles takes place, the decisionistic model of the mediation between science and politics becomes technocratic. In the technocratic model, political debates and votes are ultimately replaced by the logic of facts; politics fulfils a mere stopgap function on the way towards an ever-increasing rationalization of power (Habermas 1971, p. 64). Knowledge no longer serves power, as in the decisionistic model; knowledge now is power.

Max Weber's solution attempt  The German sociologist and philosopher Max Weber (1864-1920, see 1991) foresaw this tendency. As a bulwark against technocracy, he sought to strengthen the decisionistic model by reformulating it more rigorously. He tried to achieve this by conceiving of an interpretive social science that could explain (and thus rationalize) the subjective meaning of individual actions or decisions in terms of underlying motivations of people, without thereby presupposing value judgments of its own. Interpretive social science was to describe and explain value judgments but not to make or justify them. In this limited sense it could then support subjective decisions or actions and promote their rationality. Rather like Hobbes, Weber thus found that decisions or actions indeed admit of scientific explanation, namely, insofar as they can be shown to represent a "purpose-rational" pursuit of motivations.

At the bottom of this view is a concept that has remained very influential to this day, Weber's means-end dichotomy. It says that decisions on ends and the choice of means can be separated, in that the latter do not require value judgments of their own and hence are accessible to scientific support. This concept of purposive-rationality permits a rational choice of efficacious means; but it cannot deal with the rationality of the purposes they serve, much less ensure it. In this respect it falls back onto the very decisionism it was meant to overcome or to "rationalize."

Quite in the tradition of Hobbes, Weber in effect relegated the choice of ends once again to a domain of genuinely irrational – because subjective and value-laden – political and ethical "decisions." Weber was willing to pay this price since he hoped to achieve a critical purpose: lest it become technocratic, science should not misunderstand itself as a source of legitimation for value judgments on ends. That was the essential concern that his famous slogan cited above meant to capture: "Politics is out of place in the lecture-room." (Weber, 1991, p. 145).

The problem with this self-restriction of science is not only that the question of proper ends remains unanswered – the effectiveness and efficiency of means, when used for the wrong ends, brings about not more but less rational practice. The problem is also, and more fundamentally, that it does not achieve its critical intent, as self-restriction to questions of means does not in fact keep research free of value implications. The reason is that alternative means to reach a given end may have different practical implications for those affected by the measures taken. For example, alternative proposals for radioactive waste disposal may impose different risks and costs on different population groups, including future generations. That is to say, decisions about means, just like decisions about ends, have a value content that is in need of both ethical reflection and democratic legitimation. Whether or not their claim to purposive-rationality is backed by science makes little difference in this regard.

Weber's conception of a value-free, interpretive social science breaks down as soon as one admits this implication. Once this is clearly understood, it seems almost unbelievable how uncritically a majority of contemporary social and applied scientists still adhere to the dogma that means and ends are substantially distinct categories, so that only decisions on "ends" are supposed to involve value judgments while the choice of "means" is understood to be value-neutral with regard to given ends, that is, to be the legitimate business of science (cf. Ulrich, 1983, p. 72).

The pragmatist model of Jurgen Habermas  In order to overcome the shortcomings of both the decisionistic and the technocratic models of relating theory and practice, we need another model. Such a model will have to replace the faulty means-end dichotomy by a fundamentally complementary understanding of means and ends, just as of theory and practice (cf. Ulrich, 1983, pp. 222 and 274; 1988, pp. 146-149; 1993, p. 590; 2011, pp. 13-18). In this model, the selection of means and the selection of ends are not separable, for the rationality of either depends on the rationality of the other. Moreover, each decision has a value content of its own, although this value content again is not independent of the value content of the other decision. It is the merit of Jurgen Habermas (1971) to have elaborated a model that conforms to these requirements. He calls it the pragmatist model.

In the pragmatist model, neither politicians nor researchers possess an exclusive domain of genuine competence, nor can either side dominate the other. Caught in an intricate "dialectic of potential and will" (Habermas, 1971, p. 61), they depend on each other for the selection of both means and ends. The strict separation between their functions is replaced by a critical interaction, and the medium for this interaction is discourse. Its task is to guarantee not only an adequate translation of practical needs into technical questions, but also of technical answers into practical decisions (cf. Habermas, 1971, p. 70f).

In order to achieve this double task, the discourse between politicians and researchers must, according to Habermas (1979), be rational (or "rationally motivated") in the terms of his ideal model of rational discourse. That is, the discourse must be "undistorted" and "free from oppression." The difficulty is, once again, that we are dealing with an ideal. Even where the discourse between politicians and experts occasionally results in an undisputed consensus, how can we ever be sure that the consensus is not merely factual rather than rational? Realistically speaking, we can never be sure; for the discourse would then have to include not only the effectively involved politicians and researchers but all those who are actually or potentially concerned or affected by the decision in question, including the unborn or other parties that cannot speak for themselves. Moreover, it would have to enable all of them to play a competent role. The pragmatist model thus leads us back to the fundamental concern of critical systems heuristics, namely, that we need to develop a practicable and non-elitist "critical solution" (rather than a complete "positive solution") to the unachievable quest for securing rational practice.

Before we turn to this idea of an at least critical solution of the problem of practical reason, let us summarize our findings with respect to a competent researcher's understanding of the relationship of theory and practice: a competent researcher will (1) examine critically the role she or he is expected to play in respect to practice; (2) analyze which model of the relation of theory and practice is factually assumed in her or his mandate, and which model might be most adequate to the specific situation at hand; and (3), where the appropriate answer appears to consist in working toward a pragmatist model, a competent researcher will seek to consider all those people actually or potentially affected and, to the extent that their actual participation is feasible, will also seek to put them in a situation of competence rather than their usual situation of (supposed) incompetence.

The Critical Turn  The "critical turn" is the quintessence of much of what I have tried to say in this essay. The quest for competence in research and professional practice entails epistemological and ethical requirements that we cannot hope to satisfy completely. I am thinking particularly of requirements such as identifying all conceivable "practical implications" of a proposition; assuming proper boundary judgments; securing high-quality observations as well as compelling argumentation; dealing properly with the practical and normative (ethical, moral) dimension of our "findings and conclusions"; mediating adequately between research and practice; and facing the "challenge of the user."

In view of these and other requirements that we have briefly considered, the usual notion of competent research becomes problematic. I mean the notion that as competent researchers we ought to be able to justify our findings and conclusions in a definitive, compelling way. As an ideal, this notion of justification is certainly all right, but in practice it tempts us (or those who adopt our findings and conclusions) into raising claims to validity that no amount of research competence can possibly justify.

I suggest that we associate the quest for competence with a more credible notion of justification. First of all, let us acknowledge openly and clearly that we cannot, as a rule, sufficiently justify the results of our research. This need not mean that we should renounce any kind of validity claims, say, regarding the quality of our observations or the rationality of our conclusions. The fact that we cannot fully justify such claims does not mean that we cannot at all distinguish between higher and lower quality, or more or less compelling argumentation. It means, rather, that the manner in which we formulate and handle validity claims will have to change. We must henceforth qualify such claims very carefully, by explaining to what extent and how exactly they depend on assumptions or may have implications that we cannot fully justify as researchers, but can only submit to all those concerned for critical consideration, discussion, and ultimately, choice.

Towards a new ethos of justification  It is the researcher's responsibility, then, to make sure that the necessary processes of debate and choice can be handled by the people concerned in as competent a way as possible. To this end, a competent researcher will strive to give those concerned all the relevant information as to how her or his findings came about and what they may mean to different parties. Moreover, it becomes a hallmark of competence for the researcher to undertake every conceivable effort to put those concerned in a situation of meaningful critical participation rather than of incompetence.

This is the basic credo of the critical turn that I advocate in our understanding of research competence. It amounts to what elsewhere (Ulrich, e.g., 1984, pp. 326-328, and 1993, p. 587) I have called a "new ethos of justification," namely, the idea that the rationality of applied inquiry and design is to be measured not by the (impossible) avoidance of justification deficits but by the degree to which it deals with such deficits in a transparent, self-critical, and self-limiting way.

Since in any case we cannot avoid justification deficits, we should seek to understand competence as an effort to deal self-critically with the limitations of our competence, rather than trying to avoid or even conceal them. The critical turn demands from researchers a constant effort to be "on the safe side" of what they can assume and claim in a critically tenable way. It demands a Socratic sense of modesty and self-limitation even where others may be willing to grant the researcher the role of expert or guarantor. Once you have grasped this meaning of the critical turn, it will become an irreversible personal commitment. Kant, the father of Critical Philosophy, said it well:

This much is certain, that whoever has once tasted critique will be ever after disgusted with all dogmatic twaddle. (Kant, 1783, p. 190).

I invite you to "taste critique" and to give it a firmly established place in your notion of competence!

Tasting critique  As students of systemic research and practice, you might begin this critical effort by understanding the systems idea critically, that is, using it as a tool of reflective research and practice rather than a basis for claiming any kind of special rationality and expertise (e.g., in handling tasks of systems analysis, design, and management, or any kind of professional intervention with a systemic outlook). Thus understood, the critical turn will change the way in which we employ systems concepts and methodologies and in fact, any other methodologies. Rather than understanding systems thinking as a ground for raising claims to rationality and expertise, or even some kind of superior "systemic" rationality, we shall understand it from now on as tools for critical reflection. In other words, we will use it more for the purpose of finding questions than for finding answers.

A crucial idea that can drive the process of questioning is that of a systematic unfolding of both the empirical and the normative selectivity of (alternative sets of) boundary judgments, that is, of how the "facts" and "values" we recognize change when we alter the considered system (or situation) of concern. I have referred to this process earlier in this paper as a process of systematic boundary critique.

Two core concepts of boundary critique that I have often used to explain the idea are the "eternal triangle" of observations, valuations, and boundary judgments, and the related concept of a "systemic triangulation" of our findings and conclusions (or related claims). Interested readers will find two introductory essays that are written for a wide audience of researchers, professional people, decision-makers, and citizens in Ulrich (2000 and 2017).

A third key concept of boundary critique that I would like to mention here concerns the way boundary critique can help promote a better "symmetry of critical competence" among people with different backgrounds and concerns – those who in a project have the say and those who don't; those involved and those affected but not involved; experts and non-experts; professionals and the citizens they are supposed to serve. The basic point should by now be clear: whatever skills in the use of research methods, theoretical knowledge, and professional experience or any other kind of expertise a researcher may possess – when it comes to boundary judgments, researchers are in no better position than other people. Whoever claims the (objective) validity of some findings or the (superior) rationality of the conclusions derived from them without at the same time explaining the specific boundary judgments on which these claims depend, can thus be shown to be arguing on slippery grounds.

Boundary critique for citizens  Based on this concept of a fundamental symmetry of competence in regard to boundary judgments, boundary critique can also serve as a restraint upon unwarranted claims on the part of researchers or other people who do not employ systems concepts and methodologies (or any other methodologies) as self-critically as we might wish. If reflective research practice is not to remain dependent solely on the good will of researchers and professionals, it is indeed important that other people can challenge their findings and conclusions by making visible the boundary judgments on which they rely. See Ulrich (1993) for a fuller account of this important implication of boundary critique. Readers will also find this tool described in my writings in terms of an "emancipatory employment of boundary judgments" or shorter, of "emancipatory boundary critique" (e.g., 1996a, 1987, 2000, 2003).

I believe that ordinary people, provided they receive an adequate introduction to the idea of boundary judgments, can understand the conditioned nature of all findings and conclusions and can then also learn to challenge unwarranted claims on the part of experts in an effective way, without depending on any special expert knowledge that would not be available to them. No special expertise is required because no positive claims to validity are involved; it is quite sufficient for such critical argumentation to show that a claim relies on some crucial boundary judgments (say, as to what "improvement" means and for whom it should be achieved) that has not been laid open and for which there are options.

The employment of boundary judgments for merely critical purposes has this extraordinary power because it is a perfectly rational form of argumentation: its relevance and validity cannot be disputed simply by accusing the critic of lacking expert knowledge. For this reason I am convinced that it is able to give not only researchers and professionals but also ordinary citizens a new sense of competence. I have explained this emancipatory significance of the concept of boundary judgments elsewhere in more detail and in various terms, partly also in terms of Kant's (1787) fundamental concept of the "polemical" employment of reason (see, e.g., Ulrich, 1983, pp. 301-314; 1984, pp. 341-345; 1987, p. 281f; 1993, pp. 599-605; 1996a, pp. 41f; 2000, pp. 257-260; and 2003, pp. 329-339). But as I just hinted, you do not need to become an expert of CSH to understand and practice the idea of boundary critique.

Conclusion  At the outset I proposed that to "understand" means to be able to formulate a question. I suggested that in order to become a competent researcher, it might be a good idea for you to reflect on the fundamental question to which your personal quest for competence should respond.

I hope I have made it sufficiently clear in this paper that you will have to find this question yourself. Nobody else can do it for you. In order to assist you in this endeavor, I have tried to offer a few topics for reflection. There are, of course, many other topics you might consider as well; my choice may perhaps serve as a starting point for finding other issues you find important for developing your notion of competence.

I also proposed at the outset that for some of you, systems thinking might be part of the answer. But should it? Well, I am inclined to say, it depends: if you are ready to take the critical turn and to question the ways in which systems thinking can increase your competence, then it might indeed become a meaningful part of your personal understanding of competence. By reflecting on what might be the fundamental question to which a critical systems perspective gives part of the answer, you might begin to understand more clearly what exactly you expect to learn from studying systems thinking and how this should contribute to your personal quest for competence.

I did not promise you that it would be easy to formulate this fundamental question. It may well be that only by hindsight, towards the end of your professional life, you will really be able to define it. In the meantime, it will be necessary to rely on some tentative formulations, and more importantly, to keep searching. Only if your mind keeps searching for the one meaningful question can you hope to recognize it when you encounter it. Sooner or later you will find at least a preliminary formulation that proves meaningful to you.

My basic question (an example)  Perhaps you wish you had an example. Should I share my tentative question with you? At the end of this essay, I hope you are sufficiently prepared not to mistake it for your own question. I first encountered this fundamental question in the year 1976, when I moved to the University of California at Berkeley (UCB) to study with West Churchman, who had helped to pioneer the fields of operations research and management science in the 1950s and then, since the 1960s, became a pioneer and leading philosopher of the systems approach. Churchman used to begin his seminars with a question! He then asked his students to explore the meaning of that question with him, and that's what I have kept doing ever since. This is what Churchman wrote up on the blackboard:

Can we secure improvement
in the
human condition
by means of the
human intellect?

For Churchman, each one of the underlined key expressions in the question – "secure," `"improvement," "human condition," and "human intellect" – pointed to the need for a holistic understanding of the systems approach. We cannot hope to achieve their fulfillment without a sincere quest for "sweeping in" (Singer, 1957; Churchman, 1982, pp. 117, 125-133; cf. my appreciations in Ulrich, 1994 and 2004, pp. 1126-1128) all aspects of an issue that might conceivably be relevant, that is, ideally, for "understanding the whole system" (Churchman, 1968, p. 3). Churchman's life-long quest to understand the question thus led him to see the systems approach as a heroic effort. A systems researcher or planner who is determined to live up to the implications of the question is bound to become a hero!

My own endeavor to come to terms with the question was a little less heroic. For me, each of the question's key expressions points to the need for a critical turn of the systems approach. We cannot hope to do justice to them without a persistent, self-reflective effort to consider the ways in which we fail to be sufficiently holistic. Since boundary judgments are always in play, all our attempts to secure knowledge, understanding, and improvement are bound to be selective rather than comprehensive. We must, then, replace the quest for comprehensiveness with a more modest, but practicable, quest for boundary critique. This is why in my work on CSH, the principle of boundary critique had to replace the sweep-in principle as a methodological core concept of competent research and practice (Ulrich, 2004, p. 1128).

At least in hindsight, Churchman's question makes it easier for me to understand why I had to struggle so much to clarify my understanding of the systems idea, and why I ended up with something like critical systems heuristics and its central concept of boundary critique. It is because I tried, and still try, to understand systemic research and practice so that it responds to that fundamental question. There is no definitive answer to the question, of course; but that surely does not dispense me (or us, inasmuch as you agree) from struggling to gain at least some critical competence in dealing with it.

I wish you success in your quest for competence.

 

 

Notes

1) The British philosopher, historian, and archaeologist R.G. Collingwood (1939/1983, 1946) was perhaps the first author to systematically discuss the logic of question and answer as a way to understand the meaning of everyday or scientific propositions. As he explains in his Autobiography (1939):

I began by observing that you cannot find out what a man means by studying his spoken or written statements, even though he has spoken or written with perfect command of language and perfectly truthful intention. In order to find out his meaning you must also know what the question was (a question in his mind, and presumed by him to be in yours) to which the thing he has said or written was meant as an answer.
   It must be understood that question and answer, as I conceived them, are strictly correlative.… [But then,] if you cannot tell what a proposition means unless you know what question it is meant to answer, you will mistake its meaning if you make a mistake about that question.… [And further,] If the meaning of a proposition is correlative to the question it answers, its truth must be relative to the same thing. Meaning, agreement and contradiction, truth and falsehood, none of these belonged to propositions in their own right, propositions by themselves; they belonged only to propositions as the answers to questions. (Collingwood, 1939/1978, pp. 31 and 33, italics added) 

While remaining rather neglected in fields such as science theory and propositional logic, it was in the philosophy of history (the main focus of Collingwood, esp. 1946), along with hermeneutics (Gadamer, 2004), and argumentation theory (Toulmin, 1978, 2003) that Collingwood's notion of the logic of question and answer was to become influential. In hermeneutic terms, the questions asked are an essential part of the hermeneutical horizon that shapes what we see as possible answers and what meaning and validity we ascribe to them. In his seminal work on hermeneutics, Truth and Method, Gadamer (2004) notes:

Interpretation always involves a relation to the question that is asked of the interpreter.… To understand a text means to understand this question.… We understand the sense of the text only by acquiring the horizon of the question – a horizon that, as such, necessarily includes other possible answers. Thus the meaning of a sentence … necessarily exceeds what is said in it. As these considerations show, then, the logic of the human sciences is a logic of the question.
   Despite Plato we are not very ready for such a logic. Almost the only person I find a link with here is R.G. Collingwood. In a brilliant and telling critique of the Oxford "realist" school, he developed the idea of a logic of question and answer, but unfortunately never elaborated it systematically. He clearly saw that … we can understand a text only when we have understood the question to which it is an answer. (Gadamer, 2004, p. 363)  [BACK]

2) As I found out after writing the original working paper (Ulrich, 1998a), the phrase "death of the expert" is not mine. White and Taket (1994) had used it before. By the time I prepared the expanded version of the essay for Systems Research and Behavioral Science (Ulrich, 2001a), I had become aware of their earlier use of the phrase and accordingly gave a reference to it. My discussion here remains independent of theirs, but I recommend readers to consult their different considerations as well.  [BACK]

3) We'll return to this issue under the heading of "methodological pluralism" below. For a systematic account and critique of the identification of critical practice with methodology choice in this strand of critical systems thinking (CST), see Ulrich (2003) and the ensuing discussions in several subsequent "Viewpoint" sections of the journal. Readers not familiar with CST may find Ulrich (2012e or 2013b) useful preparatory reading.  [BACK]

4) I have given an extensive critical account of Weber's notion of "value-free" interpretive social science and his underlying conception of rationality elsewhere, see Ulrich (2012b). We will return to Weber's "interpretive social science" in the section on theory and practice below.  [BACK]

5) I use the term "boundary critique" as a convenient short label for the underlying, more accurate concept of a "critical employment of boundary judgments." The latter is more accurate in that it explicitly covers two very different yet complementary forms of "dealing critically with boundary judgments." It can be read as intending both a self-reflective handling of boundary judgments (being critical of one's own boundary assumptions) and the use of boundary judgments for critical purposes against arguments that do not lay open the boundary judgments that inform them (arguing critically against hidden or dogmatically imposed boundary assumptions). By contrast, the term "boundary critique" suggests active criticism of other positions and thus, as I originally feared, might be understood only or mainly in the second sense. While this second sense is very important to me, the first sense is methodologically more basic and must not be lost. I would thus like to make it very clear that I always intend both meanings, regardless of whether I use the original full concept or the later short term.

Terms do not matter so much and represent no academic achievement by themselves, only the concepts or ideas for which they stand do and these should accordingly be clear. The concept of a critical employment of boundary judgments in its mentioned, double meaning embodies the methodological core principle of my work on critical systems heuristics (CSH) and accordingly can be found in all my writings on CSH from the outset (e.g., Ulrich, 1983, 1984, 1987, 1988, 1993, etc.). Only later, beginning in 1995, I have introduced the short label "boundary critique" (see, e.g., Ulrich, 1995, pp. 13, 16-18, 21; 1996a, pp. 46, 50, 52; 1996b, pp. 171, 173, 175f; 1998b, p. 7; 2000, pp. 254-266; and 2001, pp. 8, 12, 14f, 18-20, 24). Meanwhile I have increasingly come to find it a very convenient label indeed, so long as it is clear that both meanings are meant (and in this sense I use it as a rule). Accordingly I am now employing it regularly and systematically (cf., e.g., Ulrich, 2002, 2003, 2005, 2006a, 2012 b, c, d; 2013b; and most recently, 2017).  [BACK]

6) The boundary questions presented here are formulated so that the second part of each question defines the boundary category at issue. For introductions of varying depth and detail to the boundary categories and questions of CSH, see, e.g., Ulrich, 1983, esp. pp. 240-264; 1984, pp. 333-344; 1987, p. 279f; 1993, pp. 594-599; 1996a, pp. 19-31, 43f; 2000, pp. 250-264; 2001a, pp. 250-264; and 2001b, pp. 91-102. On CSH in general, as well as the way it informs my two research programs on "critical systems thinking (CST) for citizens" and on "critical pragmatism," also consult: Ulrich 1988, 2000, 2003, 2006a, b, 2007a, b, 2012b, c, d, 2013b, and 2017, and Ulrich and Reynolds, 2010.  [BACK]

7) I should note that strictly speaking, observer-independence does not imply that objects are non-constructed; it only implies transferability in the sense of the above-mentioned requirement of conventional high-quality observations. I understand de Zeeuw's language as referring to ideal types of "objects" only, ideal types that may help us understand the historical and present development of science but which do not necessarily exist as such in the actual practice of science. Nor would I equate them with philosophically unproblematic notions of scientific objects. The notion of "non-constructed objects" in particular appears to be tenable only within a philosophically uncritical realism or empiricism. On more critical grounds, it would appear that all objects are constructed; indeed, even the celestial bodies of astronomy are constructed as "stars," "moons," "solar systems," "constellations," "comets," etc., before they are conceptually subsumed under one or several classes of celestial objects. Taking the example of "comets," they were not always construed as celestial bodies but earlier were seen as phenomena of the atmosphere, a change of conception that betrays the constructive side of objects.  [BACK]

8) I have discussed de Zeeuw's ideas and the way I relate them to my work on CSH in a bit more detail in Ulrich, 2012a. Basically, I see in the two frameworks two complementary approaches to the need for extending and developing the contemporary concepts of science and research practice.  [BACK]

9) The concepts of a "critical turn" of our understanding of competence, professionalism, rationality, and so on, and, related to it, of securing at least a "critical solution" to the problems of reason (particularly the unresolved problem of practical reason and the impossible quest for comprehensiveness or "systems rationality"), are as fundamental to my work on critical heuristics, critical systems thinking for citizens, reflective practice, and critical pragmatism as is the concept of boundary critique (cf. note 5 above). See, e.g., Ulrich, 1983, pp. 20f, 36, 153-157, 176f, 222-225, 265f and passim; 1993, p. 587; 1996, p. 11f; 2001, pp. 8, 11, 14f, 20, 22-25; 2003, p. 326f; 2006a, pp. 53, 57, 70f, and 73-80; 2007a, pp. 1112, 1114; 2012c, pp. 1237, 1244; and 2012d, pp. 1313-1316, 1318, 1320).  [BACK]

10) The following short account of the history of thought on the mediation of theory and practice (or science and politics) is based on my earlier, more substantial discussion of "The Rise of Decisionism" in Critical Heuristics (Ulrich, 1983, pp. 67-79). Readers who wish I had provided a more detailed account here in the present essay should consult that earlier text. In addition, a classical essay on the topic that I recommend, and which has strongly influenced by thinking on the matter, is "The scientization of politics and public opinion" by Jurgen Habermas in his Toward a Rational Society (see Habermas, 1971, pp. 62-80).  [BACK]

 

 

 

References (for Parts 1 and 2)

Note: The number of references listed in this bibliography to my own writings may suggest a lack of modesty that is not intended. It is motivated by the circumstance that this essay is of a didactic nature and that my teaching has always been based mainly on my own writings, as these are the ideas I can convey to the students in the most authentic and reflecting ways. As I hope the essay shows, no disregard for the ideas of other writers is intended; quite the contrary, it seeks to document its sources by providing the most relevant and accurate references of which I am aware, sources that have influenced me but also have been playing a seminal role in the history of ideas concerned.

Aristotle (1981). The Politics. Transl. by T.A. Sinclair, rev. by T.J. Saunders. London: Penguin (orig. ed. 1962).

Aristotle (1985). Nicomachean Ethics. Translated, with Introduction, Notes, and Glossary, by Terence Irwin. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.

Churchman, C.W. (1968). Challenge to Reason. New York: McGraw-Hill.

Churchman, C.W. (1982). Thought and Wisdom. Seaside, CA: Intersystems.

Collingwood, R.G. (1939/1978). An Autobiography. With an Introduction by Stephen E. Toulmin. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1978 (orig. 1939, without Introduction).

Collingwood, R.G. (1946). The Idea of History. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Gadamer, H.G. (2004). Truth and Method. Rev. 2nd edn., London and New York: Continuum (orig. 1975, 2nd edn. 1989; German orig. 1960, 4th edn. 1975).

Habermas, J. (1971). The scientization of politics and public opinion. In J. Habermas, Towards a Rational Society: Student Protest, Science, and Politics, Boston, MA: Beacon Press, Ch. 5, pp. 62-80.

Habermas, J. (1979). What is universal pragmatics? In J. Habermas, Communication and the Evolution of Society, Beacon Press, Boston, Mass., pp. 1-68.

Habermas, J. (1984-87). The Theory of Communicative Action. 2 vols. (Vol. 1, 1984; Vol. 2, 1987). Boston, MA: Beacon Press, and Cambridge, UK: Polity.

Jackson, M.C. (1987). Present positions and future prospects in management science. Omega, International Journal of Management Science, 15, No. 6, pp. 455-466.

Jackson, M.C. (1990). Beyond a system of system methodologies. Journal of the Operational Research Society, 41, No. 8, pp. 657-668.

Jackson, M.C. (1991). Systems Methodology for the Management Sciences. Wiley, Chichester.

Jackson, M.C. (1997). Pluralism in systems thinking and practice. In J. Mingers and A. Gill, eds., Multimethodology, Wiley, Chichester, UK, pp. 237-257.

Jackson, M.C. (1999). Toward coherent pluralism in management science. Journal of the Operational Research Society, 50, No.1, pp. 12-22.

Kant, I. (1783). Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics. 1st edn., transl. by P. Carus, rev. edn. by L.W. Beck. New York: Liberal Arts Press, 1951.

Kant, I. (1787). Critique of Pure Reason. 2nd edn., transl. by N.K. Smith. New York: St. Martin's Press, 1965.

Kant, I. (1788). Critique of Practical Reason and Other Writings in Moral Philosophy. Transl. and ed. by L.W. Beck. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1949.

Linstone, H.A. (1984). Multiple Perspectives for Decision Making. New York: North-Holland.

Linstone, H.A. (1989). Multiple perspectives: concept, applications, and user guidelines. Systems Practice, 2, No. 3, pp. 307-331.

Midgley, G. (1992). Pluralism and the legitimation of systems science. Systems Practice, 5, No. 2, pp. 147-172.

Midgley, G. (1997). Mixing methods: developing systemic intervention. In J. Mingers and A. Gill, eds., Multimethodology, Wiley, Chichester, UK, pp. 249-290.

Mingers, J., and Brocklesby, J. (1996) (eds.). Multimethodology: Towards a framework for critical pluralism. Systemist, 18, 101-132.

Mingers, J., and Gill, A. (1997) (eds.). Multimethodology: The Theory and Practice of Combining Management Science Methodologies. Chichester, UK: Wiley.

Oliga, J.C. (1988). Methodological foundations of systems methodologies. Systems Practice, 1, No. 1, pp. 87-112.

Ormerod, R. (1997). Mixing methods in practice: a transformation-competence perspective. In J. Mingers and A. Gill, eds., Multimethodology, Wiley, Chichester, UK, pp. 29-58.

Peirce, Ch.S. (1878). How to make our ideas clear. In Ch. Hartshorne and P. Weiss, eds., Collected Papers, Vol. V., Harvard Univ. Press, Cambridge, Mass., 2nd ed. 1969, pp. 248-271.

Popper, K.R. (1959). The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London: Hutchinson. New edn. London: Routledge, 2002 (German orig. 1935).

Popper, K.R. (1963). Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

Popper, K.R. (1972). Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.

Singer, E.A. Jr. (1957). Experience and Reflection (C.W. Churchman, ed.). Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania Press.

Strawson, P.F. (1964). "Truth." In G. Pitcher, ed., Truth, Englewood Cliffs, N.J: Prentice-Hall, pp. 32-53.

Toulmin, S.E. (1978). Introduction. In R.G. Collingwood, The Idea of History, Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, pp. ix-xix.

Toulmin, S.E. (2003). The Uses of Argument. Updated edn. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press (orig. 1958).

Ulrich, W. (1983). Critical Heuristics of Social Planning: A New Approach to Practical Philosophy. Bern, Switzerland, and Stuttgart, Germany: Paul Haupt. Pb. reprint edn., Chichester, UK, and New York: Wiley, 1994 (same pagination).

Ulrich, W. (1984). Management oder die Kunst, Entscheidungen zu treffen, die andere betreffen. Die Unternehmung, Schweizerische Zeitschrift für betriebswirtschaftliche Forschung und Praxis / Swiss Journal of Business Research and Practice, 38, No. 4, pp. 326-346.

Ulrich, W. (1987). Critical heuristics of social systems design. European Journal of Operational Research, 31, No. 3, pp. 276-283. Reprinted in M.C. Jackson, P.A. Keys and S.A. Cropper, eds., Operational Research and the Social Sciences, New York: Plenum Press, 1989, pp. 79-87, and in R.L. Flood and M.C. Jackson, eds., Critical Systems Thinking: Directed Readings, Chichester, UK, and New York: Wiley, 1991, pp. 103-115.

Ulrich, W. (1988). Systems thinking, systems practice, and practical philosophy: a program of research. Systems Practice, 1, No. 2, pp. 137-163. Reprinted in R.L. Flood and M.C. Jackson, eds., Critical Systems Thinking: Directed Readings, Chichester, UK, and New York: Wiley, 1991, pp. 245-268.

Ulrich, W. (1993). Some difficulties of ecological thinking, considered from a critical systems perspective: a plea for critical holism. Systems Practice, 6, No. 6, pp. 583-611.
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/ulrich_1993.pdf (post-publication version of 2006)

Ulrich, W. (1994). Can we secure future-responsive management through systems thinking and design? Interfaces, 24, No. 4, 1994, pp. 26-37). Rev. version of 20 March 2009 (last updated 14 Dec 2009) in Werner Ulrich's Home Page, Section "A Tribute to C. West Churchman."
[HTML]
http://wulrich.com/frm.html
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/ulrich_1994.pdf

Ulrich, W. (1995). Critical Systems Thinking for Citizens: A Research Proposal. Research Memorandum No. 10, Centre for Systems Studies, University of Hull, Hull, UK, 28 November 1995.

Ulrich, W. (1996a). A Primer to Critical Systems Heuristics for Action Researchers. Hull, UK: Centre for Systems Studies, University of Hull, Hull, 31 March 1996.

Ulrich, W. (1996b). Critical systems thinking for citizens. In R.L. Flood and N.R.A. Romm, eds., Critical Systems Thinking: Current Research and Practice, New York: Plenum, pp. 165-178.

Ulrich, W. (1998a). If Systems Thinking is the Answer, What is the Question? Working Paper No. 22, Lincoln School of Management, University of Lincolnshire & Humberside (now University of Lincoln), June 1998.
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/ulrich_1998b.pdf

Ulrich, W. (1998b). Systems Thinking as if People Mattered: Critical Systems Thinking for Citizens and Managers. Working Paper No. 23, Lincoln School of Management, University of Lincolnshire & Humberside (now University of Lincoln), Lincoln, UK, June 1998.
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/ulrich_1998c.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2000). Reflective practice in the civil society: the contribution of critically systemic thinking. Reflective Practice, 1, No. 2, pp. 247-268.
[DOI]
http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/713693151 (restricted access)
[PDF] http://wulrich.com/downloads/ulrich_2000a.pdf (prepublication version)

Ulrich, W. (2001a). The quest for competence in systemic research and practice. Systems Research and Behavioral Science, 18, No. 1, pp. 3-28.
[PDF]
 https://www.academia.edu/10634401/The_quest_for_competence... (restricted access)
[PDF] 
http://wulrich.com/downloads/ulrich_2001a.pdf (prepublication version, open access)

Ulrich, W. (2001b). Critically systemic discourse. A discursive approach to reflective practice in ISD, Part 2. Journal of Information Technology Theory and Application, 3, No. 3, pp. 85-106.
[HTML]
http://aisel.aisnet.org/jitta/vol3/iss3/10/ (restricted access)
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/ulrich_2001c.pdf (orig. edn., author's copyright)

Ulrich, W. (2002). Boundary critique. In H.G. Daellenbach and R.L. Flood, eds., The Informed Student Guide to Management Science, London: Thomson, 2002, pp. 41-42.
[HTML]
http://wulrich.com/boundary_critique.html (postpublication version)

Ulrich, W. (2003). Beyond methodology choice: critical systems thinking as critically systemic discourse. Journal of the Operational Research Society, 54, No. 4,  pp. 325-342.
[DOI]
http://dx.doi.org/10.1057/palgrave.jors.2601518 (restricted access)

Ulrich, W. (2004). C. West Churchman, 1913-2004. Obituary. Journal of the Operational Research Society, 55, No. 11, pp. 1123-1129.

Ulrich, W. (2006a). Critical pragmatism: a new approach to professional and business ethics. Interdisciplinary Yearbook of Business Ethics, Vol. 1, ed. by L Zsolnai. Oxford, UK, and Bern, Switzerland: Peter Lang, pp. 53-85.

Ulrich, W. (2006b). A plea for critical pragmatism. (Reflections on critical pragmatism, Part 1). Ulrich's Bimonthly, September-October 2006.
[HTML]
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_september2006.html
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_september2006.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2006c). Rethinking critically reflective research practice: beyond Popper's critical rationalism. Journal of Research Practice, 2, No. 2, 2006, Article P1.
[HTML] http://jrp.icaap.org/index.php/jrp/article/view/64/63
[PDF]
http://jrp.icaap.org/index.php/jrp/article/view/64/120 or
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/ulrich_2006k.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2007a). Philosophy for professionals: towards critical pragmatism. Journal of the Operational Research Society, 58, No. 8, 2007, pp. 1109-1113. Rev. postpublication version in Ulrich's Bimonthly, March-April 2016 (Reflections on Critical Pragmatism, Part 7).
[HTML]
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_march2016.html (rev. postpublication version)
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_march2016.pdf (rev. postpubl. version)

Ulrich, W. (2007b). The greening of pragmatism (iii): the way ahead. (Reflections on critical pragmatism, Part 6). Ulrich's Bimonthly, September-October 2007.
[HTML]
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_september2007.html
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_september2007.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2009a). Reflections on reflective practice (6a/7): Communicative rationality and formal pragmatics – Habermas 1. Ulrich's Bimonthly, September-October 2009 (7 September 2009).
[HTML] 
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_september2009.html
[PDF] 
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_september2009.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2009b). Reflections on reflective practice (6b/7): Argumentation theory and practical discourse – Habermas 2. Ulrich's Bimonthly, November-December 2009 (1 November 2009).
[HTML] 
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_november2009.html
[PDF] 
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_november2009.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2011). What is good professional practice? Part 1: Introduction. Ulrich's Bimonthly, March-April 2011.
[HTML] 
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_march2011.html
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_march2011.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2012a). Research, practice, and research practice. Ulrich's Bimonthly, March-April 2012.
[HTML]
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_march2012.html
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_march2012.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2012b). What is good professional practice? Part 3: The quest for rational action. Ulrich's Bimonthly, May-June 2012..
[HTML]
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_may2012.html
[PDF] 
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_may2012.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2012c). Operational research and critical systems thinking – an integrated perspective. Part 1: OR as applied systems thinking. Journal of the Operational Research Society, 63, No. 9, pp. 1228-1247.
[DOI] http://dx.doi.org
http:///1http://0.1057/jors.2011.141 (restricted access)
[HTML]
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_july2016.html (post-publication version, open access)
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/ulrich_2012d_prepub.pdf (prepublication version)

Ulrich, W. (2012d). Operational research and critical systems thinking – an integrated perspective. Part 2: OR as argumentative practice. Journal of the Operational Research Society, 63, No. 9, pp. 1307-1322.
[DOI]
http://dx.doi.org/10.1057/jors.2011.145 (restricted access)
[HTML]
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_september2016.html (post-publication version, open access)
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/ulrich_2012e_prepub.pdf (prepublication version)

Ulrich, W. (2012e). CST's two ways: a concise account of critical systems thinking. Ulrich's Bimonthly, November-December 2012.
[HTML]
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_november2012.html
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_november2012.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2013a). Reflections on reflective practice (6c/7): Discourse ethics and deliberative democracy, or the difficult path to communicative practice – Habermas 3 (1st half). Ulrich's Bimonthly, May-June 2013 (18 June 2013).
[HTML] 
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_may2013.html
[PDF] 
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_may2013.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2013b). Critical systems thinking. In S.I. Gass and M.C. Fu, eds., Encyclopedia of Operations Research and Management Science, 3rd edn., 2 vols. New York: Springer, Vol. 1, pp. 314-326.
[DOI]
http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4419-1153-7_1149 (restricted access)
[HTML]
http://link.springer.com/referenceworkentry/10.1007/978-1-4419-1153-7_1149 (restricted access)

Ulrich, W. (2015). The art of interconnected thinking: Frederic Vester's biocybernetic systems approach. Werner Ulrich's Home Page, Downloads section, 21 Oct. 2015 (updated and extended version of a review first published under the title "Can nature teach us good research practice?" in Journal of Research Practice, 1, No. 1, 2005, Article R2, with a Postscript of 10 April 2008).
[PDF] https://www.academia.edu/17118263/The_art_of_interconnected_thinking...
[PDF] 
http://wulrich.com/downloads/ulrich_2015f

Ulrich, W. (2017). The concept of systemic triangulation: its intent and imagery. Ulrich's Bimonthly, March-April 2017.
[HTML]
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_march2017.html
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_march2017.pdf

Ulrich, W., and Binder, J. (1998). Armut erforschen. Zurich, Switzerland: Seismo Sozialwissenschaften und Gesellschaftsfragen.

Ulrich, W., and Reynolds, M. (2010). Critical systems heuristics. In M. Reynolds and S. Holwell, eds., Systems Approaches to Managing Change: A Practical Guide, London: Springer, in association with The Open University, Milton Keynes, UK, pp. 243-292.
[PDF]
http://www.springerlink.com/content/q0m0167621j10072/ (restricted access)
[PDF]
http://oro.open.ac.uk/21299/ (open access)

Vester, F. (2007). The Art of Interconnected Thinking: Tools and Concepts for a New Approach to Tackling Complexity. Munich, Germany: MCB Verlag (German orig.: Die Kunst vernetzt zu denken, Stuttgart, Germany, Deutsche Verlags-Anstalt 1999).

Weber, M. (1991). Science as a vocation. In H.H. Gerth and C.Wright Mills, eds., From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, new edn., London: Routledge, pp. 129-156 (orig. New York: Oxford University Press, 1946; German orig. 1919).

White, L., and Taket, A. (1994). The death of the expert. Journal of the Operational Research Society, 45, No. 7, pp.733-748.

White, L., and Taket, A. (1997). Critiquing multimethodology as metamethodology: working towards pragmatic pluralism. In J. Mingers and A. Gill, eds., Multimethodology, Wiley, Chichester, UK, pp. 379-405.

Zeeuw, G. de (1992). Soft knowledge accumulation, or the rise of competence. Systems Practice, 5, No. 2, 193-214.

Zeeuw, G. de (1995). Values, science and the quest for demarcation. Systems Research, 12, No. 1, 15-24.

Zeeuw, G. de (2001). Three phases of science: a methodological exploration." Systemica, 13, Special Issue (Nos. 1-6), 2001, pp. 433-460. Previously circulated as Second Order Organizational Research,.Working Paper No. 7, Lincoln School of Management, University of Lincolnshire & Humberside, Lincoln, UK, 1996.
[PDF]
http://cict.demon.co.uk/Threephases01.PDF

Zeeuw, G. de (2005). The acquisition of high quality experience. Journal of Research Practice, 1, No. 1, Article M2.
[HTML]
http://jrp.icaap.org/index.php/jrp/article/view/8/16
[PDF]
http://jrp.icaap.org/index.php/jrp/article/view/8/15

 

 

July 2017

Su
Mo
Tu
We
Th
Fr
Sa
 
 
  
  
 
 
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 

August 2017

Su
Mo
Tu
We
Th
Fr
Sa
 
 
1
2
 3
 4
 5
 6
 7
 8
 9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
   

 

 

Picture data  Digital photograph taken on 16 July 2013, around 8 p.m., above Lake Thun, Switzerland. ISO 320, exposure mode aperture priority with aperture f/9.9 and exposure time 1/40 seconds, exposure bias -0.67. Metering mode multi-segment, contrast low, saturation high, sharpness low. Focal length 18 mm (equivalent to 29 mm with a conventional 35 mm camera). Original resolution 5184 x 3456 pixels; current resolution 700 x 525 pixels, compressed to 103 KB.

July-August, 2017

Research landscapes can be clouded and stormy

 Research landscapes can be clouded and stormy at times 

Applied researchers need to be especially careful
as to what their quest for competence means
.

(From this essay on the nature of systemic research and practice)

Notepad for capturing personal thoughts  »

Previous Picture

Next Picture  

Personal notes:

Write down your thoughts before you forget them!
Just be sure to copy them elsewhere before leaving this page.

 

 

 

 

 

 

Last updated 10 Sep 2017 (first published 28 Aug 2017)
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_july2017.html

 

 

  

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 .